Animal Matters, Sublime Pets, and Other Posthumanist Stories Stephen Tumino
ONE
Increasing unevenness in capitalist relations which have, for
example, led to the current financial crisis, have normalized an
ethical turn in the humanities and led to "new" theories that could
account for the rising inequalities in cultural terms (Gary Hall,
New Cultural Studies).
Poststructuralism and the decentered theory of the social it
authorized lost its explanatory power with the waning of the
neoliberal consensus of deregulation and monetarist economics in the
1990s, which continue to be challenged around the world by various
anti-globalization, anti-austerity, and people's and worker's
movements for imposing measures that have produced greater global
inequality. Hardt and Negri's theory of the "multitude" that
accounts for inequality as exclusion from the circuits of
"immaterial labor," Agamben's juridical account of inequality as a
"state of exception" to democratic norms, and Rancičre's writings on
democracy as the hegemonic co-optation of the proletariat as "the
part of no-part," are prominent among the "new" theories to have
emerged in the last decade. What these theories highlight is the way
that the "knowledge economy"—the high-tech sector of production that
manufactures the cultural products that shape people's
consciousness—increases the alienation of labor and therefore the
alienation of humans from humans. Insofar as these theories account
for inequality immanently from within culture they heighten the
awareness of differences within the taken for granted notions about
what it means to be human and the way such common-sensical ideas
naturalize inequality by the denial of the humanity of "others" (as
what Agamben calls "bare life," e.g.). In more middle register
writings the discourses of cultural theory produce an uncomfortable
sense of alienation that embraces the animal as a way to overcome it
and, so, one finds Derrida and Haraway writing about how they
commune with their pets. "Pettism" is put forward as a therapeutic
response that covers over a causal theory of the increasing
inequality of cybercapitalism. It is within and between these
various discourses that the "posthumanities"—as the University of
Minnesota Press series devoted to the field is called—finds its
tutor-texts for thinking about the cultural disruptions of global
capitalism. The "post" of the posthumanities signals awareness of
not only the exclusionary basis of the concept of Man, as did (post)structuralist
post-humanist philosophy, but also represents a new sentimental
embrace of non-human otherness and a Heideggerian ethics of care as
"being-with" the animal(s) to respond to the growing social
alienation of global capitalism. As in all "posts" (postfordist,
postindustrial, poststructuralism, postmodern,... ), a cultural zone
"beyond" the conflict between capital and labor is announced that
naturalizes class inequality as the basis of human societies
(Zavarzadeh 1).
The "post" of (post)structuralist post-humanism and the "post" of
the new-er posthumanism are, despite their historical differences,
ideologically the same—they attempt to "solve" in the theoretical
imaginary contradictions that have arisen from the conflict between
capital and labor. The founding texts of (post)structuralism were of
course post-humanist but the opposition to humanism today has
changed since Derrida and Foucault's critiques of humanism in the
'60s and '70s and it is less concerned with deconstructing
logocentrism and the languages of Man as it is with the cultural
inscription of bodies around the human/animal distinction. These
discursive changes are not driven by knowledge but reflect changes
in the mode of production. (Post)structuralism—the theories premised
on linguistic play and the indeterminacy of meaning—was invested in
demonstrating that the human is not the autonomous being cognitively
self-identical to itself as represented by Humanist and
Enlightenment philosophy because such humanist notions of identity
and essence are always subject to mediation by language. It thus
criticized as logocentric humanism any conception of thought that
placed thought above discursive mediation because the unsaid
assumption of such an essentialist notion of the subject is that
language is merely a medium of communication between abstract
intelligences, as if language were simply a token or tool that
delivers the pre-determined content of thought (Derrida, "The Ends
of Man"). This earlier post-humanism represented the philosophical
position that cultural media are material and as such constitutive
of the human, rather than the opposite traditional Aristotelian
humanist idea that media represent a passive and neutral medium
through which is "expressed" the spiritual essence of Man. However,
the (post)structuralist critique of humanism has to be situated
within the social relations in order to understand its hidden class
politics.
The post-humanism of (post)structuralist theory was considered
useful and "made sense" under conditions in which the ruling class
sought to deregulate the welfare-state on a global scale as these
regimes depended on the discourse of humanism to ideologically
justify their particular distribution of social resources as serving
the universal good. The humanism of welfare-state philosophy that
was dominant at that time—which Cold Warriors and Western Marxist
critics alike considered "totalitarian"—was opposed for imposing a
hegemonic unity that was exclusionary of cultural differences and
that thereby deprived the margins of a voice, or, in more common
language, individual rights. The post-humanism of difference theory
thus served to legitimate in philosophy the re-distribution and
privatization of the social resources of the state beginning in the
late 1970s that has overwhelmingly strengthened the market forces.
On the Left, the neoliberal counter-revolution that was serving to
commodify the globe was represented in terms of the politics of the
sign as heralding "new times" and laying the groundwork for a
"radical democracy" that was "liberating" the "popular" forces from
"totalitarian" power. Poststructuralism was the philosophical thug
that was used to smash the welfare-state and to portray the
privatization of social wealth during the 1980s as the basis for a
new found freedom, in much the same way that the CIA used abstract
expressionism to undermine socialist ideology after World War II
(Saunders).
Posthumanism today, by contrast, is an attempt to reconstruct a
social identity in common after the deconstruction of the human and
the crisis of inequality promoted by the policies of neoliberalism
and its post-al philosophy that announces the end of man, ideology,
and class. Theory cannot go back to humanism, which has been
delegitimated as an outdated "state philosophy" by the market
forces, but it cannot continue to defend radical difference either
because of the association of difference theory with the hegemony of
neoliberal power that helped to bring about the current global
crisis of inequality and with the more general costs associated with
global capitalism, such as the destruction to the environment, the
escalation of imperialism and war, and the general degradation of
the quality of life that come in their wake. What has emerged to
contain the contradictions of capitalism today is the posthumanism
of Derrida, Haraway, Wolfe et. al. showcased by the Minnesota Press
series, which critiques capitalism as an oppressive "biopower" that
subjugates life only to announce a new non-oppressive and
co-operative being in common—what Donna Haraway calls the "transspecies,"
Derrida calls l'animot, and Žižek, in his speech given at the
Occupy Wall Street encampment, the "biogenetic commons." In this
theory of a new post-exploitative present made of biopower and
biopolitical cultural resistance, the concept of the human is still
considered ideologically incoherent only it is not because of social
mediations that defer and delay its self-presence through spacing
which deny its purported autonomy. Rather, posthumanism now
announces the end of the human species as a distinct entity in
nature because of the emergent knowledge that the human is
genetically hybridized with non-human others (animals)—a condition
taken to be enabled by biopower, especially the knowledge practices
of biogenetics. Haraway bases her understanding of transspecies, for
example, on the fact that biogenetics has discovered that "human
genomes can be found in only about 10 percent of all the cells that
occupy the mundane space I call my body; the other 90... are filled
with the genomes of bacteria, fungi, protists, and such" (When
Species Meet 3). What contemporary posthumanism thus rejects is
not only the discourse of Man as a universalist cultural construct
that marginalizes cultural differences but also, and more
importantly, Marx's concept of human "species being," on the claim
that species-being suppresses the biological difference inscribed
within nature (in the genetic code) and thereby perpetuates the
regime of what Derrida has called "carnophallogocentrism": "the
interventionist violence that is practiced... in the service of or
for the protection of the animal, but most often the human animal" (Animal
25).
And yet, the posthumanism which "makes sense" now in terms of
legitimating class inequality is, as in the past, the one that
serves the dominant sector of capital that, among other things,
through its command of the resources of the state makes the most
profits. The posthumanism of transspeciesism and the biogenetic
commons reflects changes in property. Specifically, it reflects the
shift from forms of public wealth invested in social welfare
programs to privatized wealth and speculative capital that are more
and more invested in the biotech and "green" industries and that,
therefore, stand to make the biggest profits in the new millennium,
as these industries represent the main avenues of capital
valorization and accumulation through which capitalism is currently
commodifying the environmental crisis. Posthumanism, in short, is a
social theory after the massive privatization of the social; the
transspecies, is a "commons" founded on the continuation of
extracting surplus-value from labor and the suppression of the class
consciousness needed to end exploitation.
TWO
In his introduction to the "Posthumanities" series published by the
University of Minnesota Press, Cary Wolfe gives a map of the
posthumanities that promises to go beyond what he considers the
deadlock of contemporary cultural theory; specifically, because of
its residual humanism. Central to Wolfe's story of the
posthumanities is Derrida's "thinking concerning the animal" (The
Animal That Therefore I Am 7) as if it marked a new moment in
cultural theory beyond the regional conflicts of the past that opens
theory to more global horizons. Derrida is made to support Wolfe's
view of "posthumanism" as
that which "opposes the fantasies of disembodiment and autonomy
inherited from humanism itself" (What
Is Posthumanism? xv). What Wolfe's posthumanities series
canonizes are the texts of Derrida's later "ethical turn,"
such as The Animal That Therefore I Am, in which are found annotations of
experience and the quotidian which are represented as sublime
("secret") moments of sensual embodiment that produce a "pathetic"
(Derrida 26) version of history as existential "suffering" (26).
This is in contrast to
Derrida's earlier more analytically rigorous writings, such as his
reading of Lacan, in which, for example, is found his critique of
"embodiment" as a support of logocentric thought. I will briefly
rehearse Derrida's critique of Lacan in order to explain why
Derrida's later ethical turn to embodiment is not, as Wolfe
imagines, a "new" cutting-edge discourse but represents the dumbing-down
of theory in the service of capital.
In his response to Lacan, Derrida argued that the primacy of the signifier
that developed within psycho-analytic thought after Saussure, posits
a "speaking-subject" that sustains the "ontotheology" of
"Western metaphysics." In other words, he argued that the
"materiality" of the signifier ("voice") is used as a subordinate
and idealized ground for the telos (ends) of presence as
"speech," hence, as the condition of possibility for the traditional
idealist autonomy of the subject in Western humanism, even if
finally as a "split-subject" in Lacan (Positions 108-9). What
Wolfe turns to in Derrida is not his earlier critique of the "body"
as central to humanist idealism, but his later more sentimental
texts in which, as Derrida puts it, "animal words" (Animal
35) proliferate "in proportion as my texts... become more
autobiographical" (35). In short, Wolfe privileges writings in
which, in place of self-reflexively accounting for the conditions of
theory, Derrida instead offers mere annotations of experience. If
"humanism" is premised on maintaining a split between the material
("voice") and the conceptual ("speech") in which the former is taken
to be subordinate to the latter, as Derrida earlier argued against
Lacan, then the later Derrida, whom Wolfe invokes and who turns to
"embodiment" as a basis for the ethical, is not posthumanist but
humanist with a vengeance, hence the easy sentimentality of his
later texts and their quick canonization. In other words, Derrida
has engaged in a simple reversal of the mind/body binary, which is
central to Western humanist philosophy, that not only maintains its
terms but, more importantly, advances a cultural politics that
defines the good within the epistemic co-ordinates of the dominant
ideology in which nature is sentimentalized (as the affective) and
theory depoliticized (as ethics). It is because of this accommodation of the dominant ideology that today the "question of the animal" in Derrida's later writings is made a matter of embracing the "passion of the animal" (12). Rather than situate affective experience within the historical series, Derrida reifies experience by fetishizing the "feelings" that overtake him when his pet cat looks at him naked in the bathroom, especially the feeling of "shame" (4) at "seeing oneself seen naked under a gaze behind which there remains a bottomlessness… uninterpretable, unreadable, undecidable, abyssal and secret" (The Animal That I Therefore Am 12). "In these moments of nakedness" standing before his pet cat Derrida locates "an 'experience' of language about which one could say, even if it is not in itself 'animal,' that it is not something that the 'animal' could be deprived of" (166), which he puts forward as an ethical model of what he claims is "the most radical means of thinking the finitude that we share with animals" (28). Leaving aside that what Derrida is here calling an experience of finitude is really not an experience but a trope for his commitment to Saussure's synchronic theory of language which understands language ahistorically rather than as "an arena of class struggle" (Vološhinov 23), such an experience of bodily finitude is necessary, according to Derrida, so as to understand how the "industrial, mechanical, chemical, hormonal, and genetic violence to which man has been submitting animal life for the past two centuries" (Animal 26) shapes the cultural "inequality... between, on the one hand, those who violate not only animal life but even and also this sentiment of compassion, and, on the other hand, those who appeal to an irrefutable testimony to this pity" (28-9). In other words, it is only by embracing our animal mortality as embodied beings with singular experiences that inequality becomes intelligible, and not as a material antagonism but as a cultural "war... waged over the matter of pity" (29). On these pathetic terms, what is to be opposed most of all is speciesism because it establishes a hierarchical binary that puts "the whole animal kingdom with the exception of the human" (41) into a "vast encampment" (34) for the purpose of industrial "genocide" (26) and thus foments the culture wars over values. In nakedly communing with his pet cat Derrida thus experiences a moment of animal liberation from humanist thought in which he apparently believed "everything can happen" (12) and indulged in a kind of thinking without thinking ("the passion of the animal") that, following Heidegger's "need to strike out 'being'" (39) dismisses thinking in materialist terms about inequalities of power, which are at root class conflicts over the resources of labor inscribed in what Marx calls human "species-being" (Economic Manuscripts 68).
Derrida understands the "question of the animal" in strictly
immaterial (emotional and ethical) terms that occults humanity's
actual relation to nature. He does this work of occulting the
material labor relations that make up the human species by inventing
a hybrid "animal-word" (l'animot) through which to interpret the social conflicts over
inequality, which he considers to be primarily cultural as they are
the result of unethical practices: "the interventionist violence
that is practiced… in the service of or for the protection of the
animal, but most often the human animal" (Animal
25). L'animot is a
portmanteau combining the French terms for "animal" and "words"
which sounds the same as the plural of "animal." What this term does
in Derrida's writing is to represent recent "developments of
zoological, ethological, biological, and genetic forms of
knowledge" (25)—knowledges which are, in other words, productive
of the hi-tech commodification of hybrid forms of life that for
Haraway defy species classification and lay the basis for a "transspecies"
consciousness—as the basis for a new ethical awareness he calls the
"passion of the animal," or, "embodied knowledge" (that is made
"naked, vulnerable, and unfathomable").
L'animot, in other words,
marks a "double session" (Dissemination
191-207) that, to begin with, inverts the material (species-being)
with the immaterial (biogenetics) by showing how they include rather
than oppose each other so as to reveal their dependence on a
disavowed third term—the "passion of the animal," which is
represented as a type of "'experience' of language about which one
could say, even if it is not in itself 'animal,' that it is not
something that the 'animal' could be deprived of" (Animal
166). This "experience of language" although marked in emotional
terms and inscribed within the affective, is of course not a
spontaneous feeling brought about by humans tampering with nature,
nor is it simply an insight that came to Derrida as he communed with
his pet cat in the bathroom. In fact, the experience of language
here that is not in itself animal but is also not something we can
be sure animals do not posses is Derrida's posthumanist ethical
gloss on the differential concept of language that he gets from
Saussure but presented here in a less alienating language: language
as a structure without a subject because, "In language there are
only differences without positive terms" (Saussure 120). Derrida, in
other words, is defining animal life as inherently decentered
because subject to cultural processes of meaning production, in
which case any differences between humans and animals is a language
effect (e.g., as in the difference between philosophical and poetic
discourses about animals that Derrida discusses).
Nevertheless, although Derrida is not so crudely biologically
literal as Haraway in his notion of human-animal hybridity that in
the posthumanities signals the arrival of a post-exploitative being
in common, he still puts forward a notion of the animal that
functions as an ethical limit-text within the discourse of theory in
which the "passion of the animal" marks a liberated zone of
affective experience as if it existed outside the history of class
struggle. By "striking out being" in the "abyssal rupture" (Animal
30) of communing with his pet cat and experiencing the passion of
the animal, Derrida reinscribes a notion of history as the
determination of the material by the immaterial, as if "spirit"
moves the world rather than labor. So, on the one hand what he calls
"thought," "logocentrism" (27) or the "dominant form of consensus"
(40), because it puts "the whole animal kingdom with the exception
of the human" (41) into a "vast encampment" (34), is made
responsible for industrial "genocide" (26). And yet, the "experience
of language" that Derrida's "animal words" embody is itself a form
of "thinking the animal" more ethically as finitude, passion, shame,
vulnerability, rather than instrumentally and genocidally in the
culture "war... waged over the matter of pity" (29). In other words,
Derrida reinscribes the human/animal binary as an ethical difference
within knowledge and therefore, in the terms of his text, maintains
the same domination of the animal by the human that perpetuates the
"veritable war of the species" (31) he laments. As always,
deconstruction reinscribes what it opens to question by failing to
go outside the epistemological by implicating knowledge within the
historical series of class practices.
Insofar as l'animot marks the animal as essentially
unknowable (the sublime "secret" of the pet) it privatizes animal
life, fixing it, for ethical reasons, as a singularity unconnected
to labor relations, and this despite the fact that animal life is
historical and changes with changes in the human life which
dominates the earth. As Marx explains, "The whole character of a
species, its species-character, is contained in the character of its
life activity... Admittedly animals also produce [but] an animal
produces only itself, whilst man reproduces the whole of nature" (Economic
Manuscripts 68, 69). On Marx's logic, l'animot therefore
indexes a change in the social relations of production rather
than simply marking a singular experience humans have come to share
with animals as a result of the technological intervention into
nature. How we interact with and conceive of animal life, including
our own species being, always reflects our practical interaction
with nature within necessary social relations at a certain level of
development. Derrida's opposition of "thinking" as the liberation of
(animal) passion from the "dominant thought" of human speciesism
reinscribes the human/animal binary as internal to knowledge and
occults human species being as the
universal
production of life, what
Marx calls "life-engendering life" (Economic Manuscripts 68).
By "striking out" Marx's concept of species-being as the universal
production of life and reinscribing (non)knowledge as the basis of
life Derrida fixes the animal in the dumb muteness of an "uninterpretable,
unreadable, undecidable, abyssal… secret" (Animal
12) and mystifies the class structure on which all life on earth
depends. This is not merely a logical contradiction, however,
considering that what is being put forward as a "new" (posthumanist)
ethical thought is actually a reinscription of the body as the
biological basis of life and culture as the primary zone of
conflicts. More importantly it testifies to ongoing material
conflicts in the economic base and takes the side of the ruling
class against the workers.
While the dehierachization and reinscription of the human/animal
binary is represented as a self-enclosed movement within culture
(knowledge, ethics, affect) it is actually a mode of side-taking in
the class struggles of global capitalism against the workers who
need "outside" knowledge—the positive and reliable knowledge of
class inequality that critiques ideology—for their emancipation from
capital. Furthermore, without such class consciousness humanity will
not be able to realize a more sustainable relation to nature. It is
not the devaluing "thought" of animals in humanism that produces
their subjugation by humans—although such a "violent" understanding
of thought is necessary for deconstruction to represent the animal
as liberated by "thinking the animal"—but the exploitation of human
species-being by humans for profit that does so. More exactly, it is
the estrangement of human species-being through the capitalist
exploitation of human labor-power that produces the reified
"thought" of human superiority over nature through the exercise of
pure reason on the one hand, as well as the ethical "thinking" of
the embodied "passion" of the animal as its corrective on the other.
The closed circuit of knowledge (species thought/embodied thinking
of the animal) in Derrida's text is itself a reification of human
labor activity which considers human species-being in a one-sided
way, as "knowledge" of the body (animal life). Making animal life
into an unfathomable abyssal secret of embodiment may seem like a
challenge to the interventionist violence of "carnophallogocentrism"
(Derrida), but in its culturalism it underwrites the idea that
inequality is an effect of knowledge rather than the reverse, that
all knowledge (even the "secret" thinking that is taken to be not
thinking but feeling the passion of the animal) is rooted in the
class inequality of the capitalist mode of production and reflects
it at the level of theory—either for or against capital or labor. By
inscribing "thought" as dominant and "embodiment" as subjected (but
secretly free "thinking") Derrida normalizes the class relations
which in actuality reify knowledge of species-being as a whole, not
by humanity intellectually imposing on animals, but by imposing
animality on humans, that is, by reducing the life activity of
humans to animal life, which is the "dominion of immediate physical
need" (Marx, Economic
Manuscripts 68) imposed on humanity by capitalism.
And yet, the one-sided production of estranged labor undertaken for
wages which reduces the worker to immediate physical need so as to
increase surplus-value for the capitalist is what is today
everywhere in crisis. Behind the succession of financial bubbles and
crises of recent years (Savings & Loan, dot com, Enron, and now the
housing bubble) is the overproduction endemic to capitalism as it
"rationalizes" production so as to increase profits: the technical
innovations introduced in production to increase the surplus-value
of labor have the overall effect of decreasing the abstract
labor-time overall, which is the source of value, and this is what
encourages speculation in the financial markets because of the low
rate of return on industrial capital investment. What the crisis
shows is that the private consumption of social wealth that
regulates production for profit is coming into contradiction with
the global mass of labor which has transformed the planet, the very
process of accumulation that has "simplified the class antagonisms"
(Marx and Engels, "Manifesto,"
Reader 474) and confronts humanity with the necessity for
socialism, as even the likes of Alan Greenspan now recognize.
[1]
Marx's concept of "species-being" as the "life activity" of humans
is crucial for understanding and changing the world and it therefore
necessarily comes into conflict with the dissimulations of
capitalism such as the "abyssal difference" of the posthumanist
transspeciesism that reifies life as embodied knowledge found in
Derrida. In short, what the world is confronted with is not a
cultural "war... waged over the matter of pity" (Derrida,
Animal 29) due to the normalization of "genetic violence" against
animal life, which is a secondary cultural effect of the
exploitation of labor. Rather, the question is will the human
species be ruled by necessity so as to profit a few or realize a
world free from need by producing in accordance with the needs of
life as a whole?
As Engels' explains in "The Part Played by Labour in the Transition
from Ape to Man" it is the exploitation of human labor—which is what
is at the center of capitalism and not "genetic violence"
(Derrida)—that produces "the idealist world outlook," which defines
the human in a one-sided way as "outside" or "above" nature, such
that human nature is understood as "arising out of thought instead
of [human] needs" (Dialectics 178). Engels' observation that
the spiritual humanism of the bourgeoisie "dominates men's mind" to
such an extent that even the "materialistic natural scientists" are
"unable to form any clear idea of the origin of man" in labor has
proven prescient for understanding the cyber ideology of today in
which knowledge is made the source of value. Engels' explanation of
the dominance of ideology is embedded in a materialist understanding
of the contradictions of capitalism. He explains that while the
mastery of nature by the human species "consists in the fact that we
have the advantage over all other creatures of being able to learn
its laws and apply them correctly" in material production, this
"mastery," however, by no means is meant to suggest that men "rule
over nature like a conqueror over a foreign people, like someone
standing outside nature" (Dialectics 180). Rather, to the
contrary, as he goes on to clarify, the more social labor takes
control of natural processes the more "men not only feel but also
know their oneness with nature," and, furthermore, "the more
impossible will become the senseless and unnatural idea of a
contrast between mind and matter, man and nature, soul and body" (Dialectics
181). Capitalism, however, represents a material obstacle to such
universal development in which humans not only realize their
relation to the social world and nature but thus become free to
"produce in accordance with the standard of every species"
(Marx, Economic Manuscripts
69). While on the one hand capitalism "advances... the natural
sciences" and puts us in "a position to realize, and hence to
control, also the more remote natural consequences of at least our
day-to-day production activities" (Engels, Dialectics
180-181) on the other it "is predominantly concerned only about the
immediate, the most tangible result" of production so that "the more
remote effects of actions directed to this end turn out to be quite
different, are mostly quite the opposite in character" (Dialectics
183).
Derrida places species-being under erasure and mystifies the
relation between human and non-human life, instead inscribing the
contradictions as internal to knowledge practices. In an initial
move he first locates the question of the animal as part of an
ongoing culture war between anthropocentric discourses on the one
side, which define animals in general against an unquestioned human
norm, and the discourses of "thinking" on the other, which "strike
out being" (following Heidegger) and destabilize the traditional
binary between human/animal by posing the question of animal
"suffering" (Animal
25-28). He frames the cultural debate as a "war... waged over the
matter of pity" (29) emergent in the wake of the biotech revolution
of the last two centuries because it confronts humanity with the
ethical dilemma of the mass production of living organisms for the
sole purpose of being consumed (for food, fashion, experiments,
etc.). Having been made aware by the biogenetic intervention into
animal life that thinking is always embodied, the ensuing cultural
war necessarily "concerns what we call 'thinking'" (29) as the West
has understood it as the essence of what it means to be human. The
sides in this culture war are thus not "for" or "against" animal
rights on Derrida's framing, but for or against thinking what
Derrida calls the "abyssal difference" that structures the surface
"inequality... between, on the one hand, those who violate not only
animal life but even and also this sentiment of compassion, and, on
the other hand, those who appeal to an irrefutable testimony to this
pity" (28-9). The difference that matters, "the most radical means
of thinking" (28) on these terms, is purely a linguistic matter: how
to formulate "an 'experience' of language about which one could say,
even if it is not in itself 'animal,' that it is not something that
the 'animal' could be deprived of" and thereby bear witness to "the
passion of the animal" as resistant to thought (166).
L'animot is Derrida's neologism
to describe how bioengineered life deconstructs the binary of
human/animal from within and produces a "thinking" (that is not a
thinking but a feeling) of "the abyssal limits of the human" (Animal 12), a "passion" (without thinking) to be found in "those
moments of nakedness" (12) in the "eyes" (body) of the animal. The
new forms of life (l'animot) produced by biogenetic capitalism are thus held to
"necessitate" (29) new forms of thinking animal life that go beyond
the surface difference of inequality to uncover "abyssal
difference," a thinking without thinking, the "passion of the
animal," or "embodied thinking," "naked," "open," "vulnerable," the
"nonpower at the heart of power" (28), "the most radical means of
thinking the finitude that we share with animals" (28), and "all the
living things that man does not recognize as his fellows, his
neighbors, or his brothers" (34).
L'animot marks a zone of thinking without thinking (the affective)
as the ethical basis of whatever life beyond inequality that comes
with communing with one's pet at a time of global genocidal genetic
violence (26). However, what this "pathetic" framing of the question
silently assumes is that "knowledge" work, the production of hybrid
transspecies life forms produced by biogenetic industries, has
displaced human species-being (labor) as the base of the social. In
actuality, the production of
l'animot, whether discursively by deconstruction or concretely
in biogenetics, is itself an effect of the social relations of
production as a whole, the labor arrangements which determine our
place in nature as a collective species being. Without the knowledge
of labor as species-being ("life-engendering life," Marx) there can
be no fundamental transformation of capitalism but only cultural
reforms of its more obviously outdated practices (what Derrida calls
"violence").
For all his opposition to "historicism," Derrida ascribes the agency
of history to the history of ideas (biogenetics, philosophy,
thought, thinking, passion, Heidegger, Saussure,…) and assumes a
bottom-line technological "necessity" (Animal 29) of coming
to an ethical accommodation with inequality, rather than produce a
critique-al knowledge of the social totality as estranged labor, for
social change. Critique, unlike ethics, entails a knowledge of the
totality of the social relations of production as a whole and how
they shape signs, meanings, values, subjectivity, etc. For instance,
biogenetic technology is not an autonomous activity driven by human
egoism (whether conceived in terms of thought, knowledge, passion,
or domination), but a part of capitalist production driven by profit
which is realized from the extraction of surplus-labor from
wage-labor. Speculating on "the question of the animal"—thinking
about thought about animals but from their mysterious embodied
perspective—is not a "radical" thinking that gets at the "root" of
inequality. "The root," as Marx says, is "man himself" ("Critique of
Hegel's Philosophy" 137): humans, that is, not as "setting out from
what men say, imagine, conceive, nor from men as narrated, thought
of, imagined, conceived" but as "real, active men... on the basis of
their real life-process" (Marx and Engels,
German Ideology 42), in
short, as social animals whose life activity (labor) is universal.
In fact, Derrida's "animal-words" (l'animot) themselves
display the profit to be had in the production of ideological
hybrids and how this alienated intellectual production that puts
individual profit making before meeting people's needs naturalizes
the estranged species life of capitalism that produces the
inequality and environmental destruction in the first place, making
it seem unchangeable (because of unfathomable "abyssal differences"
in Derrida's discourse).
What Wolfe is unable to account for in his mapping of the
posthumanities with Derrida at its center is how ideas of the
material and materiality have changed in cultural theory under the
impact of changes in the structure of property. Contemporary
discourses on posthumanism represent a further fold in the canonical
post-humanist discourses found in the earlier writings of Derrida
("The Ends of Man"), Foucault ("the end of Man" announced in
The Order of Things), and
Barthes ("Death of the Author"). While the texts of
poststructuralist theory placed Man under erasure as a discursive
construct and found Western humanism to be a coerced consensus that
undermined the purported project of universal enlightenment, the
contemporary discourses of posthumanism affirm the body as a
post-ideological zone of opacity and subversive singularity (bare
life, passion of the animal, transspecies) that escapes all norms
and testifies to a "coming community" (Agamben), or, a "democracy to
come" (Derrida). The turn to the body is justified in "ethical"
terms as addressing contemporary biopower, the cultural impact of
biotech engineering and cybertech industries, on the argument that
in the wake of a new "knowledge economy" the material has changed:
textuality has hybridized with corporeality (biogenetic life) and,
as a result, the dogmas of (post)structuralist theory are made to
circulate as the self-evidence of "experience" (e.g.,
The Affective Turn or
Life on the Screen). The
"materiality of the signifier" (De Man) or the "materiality of the
letter" (Lacan) has been displaced by the "materialism of the
incorporeal" (Foucault) or the "materiality of ideology" (Žižek) in
which knowledge is held to be a singularly sublime and excessive
drive that both constitutes and disrupts the phenomenal in a
mysterious contingent way. This is a "materiality without
materialism" (Derrida, Specters of Marx) of an "event"-full historiography centered around
the "Messianic cessation of happening" (Benjamin 263) in the
everyday in which power intervenes in the daily in the form of what
Agamben calls the "state of exception" and reduces the human to
"bare life" (Homo Sacer).
What actually has changed however is not the rise of knowledge as a
constitutive power over the social but the way the State—which as
Marx and Engels say is nothing but "a committee for managing the
common affairs of the whole bourgeoisie" (The
Manifesto of the Communist Party) in their struggle against the
workers—is being used to normalize the process of capital
accumulation.
Deconstruction was useful under neoliberalism when the question for
the ruling class was how to privatize the state and increase
surplus-value from within the territory of the nation because of its
opposition to the welfare-state as the "totalitarian" imposition on
cultural differences. But now that the state has become relatively "deterritorialized"
by being subordinated to multinational corporations whose interests
are no longer limited to exploiting the territory of a nation but to
amassing surplus-value around the world, deconstruction has proven
to be irrelevant in containing the contradictions of transnational
capitalism and new-er more "ethical" theories have emerged to do so.
What changed in theory is the concept of the material.[2]
From being primarily understood as a purely textual matter ("the
materiality of the signifier," De Man) the material is now
"immaterial," a power over life that is held to exceed positive and
reliable knowledge and that can thus only be experienced bodily as a
sensual affect: whether as what Agamben calls "bare life," or as the
"biogenetic life" of Haraway's "transspecies," or, the "multitude"
of affective labor (Hardt and Negri), or in terms of personal
(in)fidelity to an unrepresentable "truth-event" (Badiou), or, as in
Žižek's notion of the Real as sublime "social substance" whose
unequal coverage constitutes class as a pathological death drive in
his texts. In these terms, what posthumanism investigates, unlike
the theoretical post-humanism dominant under early neoliberalism, is
"biopower," which Foucault argued, demands thick description of the
technological conditions that call into question the human mastery
of nature and that often times seems to place humanity's "existence
as a living being in question" (History of Sexuality 143). Žižek has even begun calling such an
approach "dialectical materialism" because of its focus on "the
'inhuman' core of the human" (Parallax
View 5) as "the gap between humanity and its
own inhuman excess" (5), which he calls the "materiality of
ideology" coincident with the "desubstantialization" of the
"commons" by the market
("Ecology").[3] The result in
terms of Žižek's understanding of history is devastating as he makes
a fetish of alienation, of how, in Marx's words, "an
inhuman
power rules over everything" (Economic
Manuscripts 110) in capitalism, whereby, as Engels adds, "the
more remote effects of actions... turn out to be... quite the
opposite in character" (Dialectics 183) of what was intended
by the producers. In doing so, Žižek redefines humanity as the
unconscious rather than
conscious species-being driven by desire not need and re-conceives
history in Benjamin's messianic terms as an inevitable path to
global catastrophe from which the only escape is a religious leap of
faith—what Žižek calls "pure voluntarism" (Tragedy
154). And yet, what is strangely missing from these discussions,
hence the continuation of the "post," is a materialist understanding
of the material as what Marx calls "species-being" (or "life
activity, productive life,"
Economic Manuscripts 69).
As Marx and Engels explain,
Men can be distinguished from animals by consciousness, by religion
or anything else you like. They themselves begin to distinguish
themselves from animals as soon as they begin to
produce their means of
subsistence. (The German
Ideology 37)
This quote needs to be read literally: What they are saying is not,
as is so often claimed, that labor, tools, production, economics,
distinguishes humans from animals instead of consciousness,
religion, or anything else you like, but rather that humans can be
philosophically distinguished from animals by anything
(including labor, tools, production, economics,…) and yet whatever
that "thing" is thought to be it necessarily is a product of human
life activity, or, human species being, rather than merely a fixed
idea. As Marx acknowledges elsewhere, "animals also produce" (Economic
Manuscripts 68) and "the life of the species, both in man and in
animals, consists physically in the fact that man (like the animal)
lives on organic nature" (67), so it is not simply production which
distinguishes humans from animals for Marx. Nevertheless, despite
Marx's recognition of the commonality, he yet maintains that human
life activity is different than animal life activity because the
life activity of humans is not completely determined for them as it
is for animals by purely biological and environmental conditions:
The animal is immediately one with its life activity. It does not
distinguish itself from it. It is
its life activity. Man
makes his life activity itself the object of his will and of his
consciousness. He has conscious life activity. It is not a
determination with which he directly merges. Conscious life activity
distinguishes man immediately from animal life activity. (Economic
Manuscripts 68)
It is important to note that it is not the natural possession of
"consciousness" that distinguishes human beings from the rest of
animal life for Marx here. Rather, it is the social mode of activity
through which human beings produce their life under diverse and
changing conditions that they have learned not only to consciously
adapt to but, as well, to transform, that does so. Human beings
confront their life activity—the "metabolism" of their own labor
mixed with natural resources—in practice as well as an object of
thought, as something they are necessarily made aware of themselves
having produced through their own labor practices over time. Human
beings in their life activity therefore confront nature not as
something given that subsists in-itself but always as a material
basis for the realization of their own purposes:
What distinguishes the worst architect from the best of bees is that
the architect builds the cell in his mind before he constructs it in
wax. At the end of every labour process, a result emerges which had
already been conceived by the worker at the beginning, hence already
existed ideally. (Marx, Capital 284)
This objectification of human life is of course a result of the fact
that human life activity (i.e., labor) transforms nature, including
human nature (e.g., language as an adaptation of natural sounds for
the purpose of communication), whereas animal life activity does
not. In other words, humans socially produce a transformation within
the material conditions they inhabit in the very process of
producing what is immediately necessary to sustain themselves
whereas animals do not. Consequently humans also produce and
transform themselves in order to adapt to the ever changing
conditions. The difference between the human and animal Marx draws
attention to throughout his writings is concretely demonstrable in
the fact that "an animal forms only in accordance with the standard
and the need of the species to which it belongs, whilst man knows
how to produce in accordance with the standard of every species" (Economic
Manuscripts 69). More importantly, however, this is also a
critique-al distinction to make between humans and animals in order
to produce awareness of how human labor, which is imposed by
material necessity and productive of the "know how" to produce all
life, is "estranged" under capitalism; the mode of production in
which "all things are other than themselves" because "an
inhuman power rules over everything" (110) due to the law of value
that emerges from out of the commodification of labor. The
objectification and transformation of our species-being may be the
basis of human life, but the commodification of labor is the
objectification of human life itself that reduces the subject of
labor herself into an object on the market that is consumed by
another who owns the means of production, for the purpose of
accumulating capital. Capitalism thus "makes man's species-life a
means to his physical existence" (69) so that humanity "produces
only under the dominion of immediate physical need" (68) rather than
"produce in freedom" (68) from necessity. In other words, capitalism
systematically expropriates abstract social labor and privatizes it
in the hands of a few and thus turns labor, the life activity of the
species, into physical work undertaken for mere subsistence. The
result is that capitalism "humanizes" nature, turning it into
material wealth, and in the process "dehumanizes" humanity by
reducing labor to a means of capital accumulation by the capitalist
and a task undertaken by the worker for wages merely to maintain her
physical existence.
It is important to clarify Marx's theory of species-being because
today—as Engels said of the "materialistic natural scientists" of
his day who were "unable to form any clear idea of the origin of
man" owing to the fact that "under ideological influence" they did
"not recognize the part played by labor therein" (Dialectics
178)—even the marxists fail to grasp it. Terry Eagleton, for
instance, has recently defended Marx's concept of species-being (After
Theory 120) but,
echoing Weber's understanding of capitalism as "spiritual" in
essence, he turns it into the useless romantic idea that human
nature inherently "resists" the capitalist ethic. According to
Eagleton, capitalism depends on a "ruthlessly instrumental logic"
(119) that demands "everything... must have its point and purpose"
(116), so as to build up the expectation of a "reward" for "acting
well" (116) and, moreover, it reserves punishments for acting in
ways that do "not have a goal" (115). In response to his culturalist
theory of capitalism he posits an equally culturalist understanding
of what is to be done to transform capitalism. When he argues that
defending the idea of "the material 'species being' of humanity"
(120) is a radical act of transgression (119) he actually puts
forward a pseudo-materialist understanding of "species-being" by
representing humanity as having a cultural root and, in turn,
representing culture as purposeless activity for its own sake.
Leaving aside for the moment the "spiritual" way Eagleton discusses
capitalism, is "the idea of fulfilling your nature" that he finds
exemplified in culture really "inimical to the capitalist success
ethic" (After Theory 110)?
Capitalism after all depends on constant technical innovation
because it realizes relative surplus value by cutting the amount of
time workers engage in necessary labor to reproduce the value
equivalent of their wages and increasing the amount of time spent in
surplus labor which forms the basis of the capitalist's profit
(Marx, Capital 340-416). To argue that "it is in our nature
to go beyond ourselves" and "give birth to culture, which is always
changeable, diverse and open ended" (After Theory 119) and thus "resistant" to
instrumentality is to naturalize the law of value that drives
capitalism by embedding the drive for innovation in human nature.
Making culture the root of humanity also homogenizes culture as
reflecting a universal "sense of belonging" (21) that "humanizes"
both oppressor and oppressed rather than a site of class antagonism
over the material resources that determine whose needs are being met
and whose are not, who is "humanized" by capital and feels at home
in the world as it is, and who is "dehumanized" by it and has
nothing to lose.
But what about Eagleton's argument that culture not only is
essentially anti-capitalist but also is the material root of human
nature and as such an incontestable "absolute truth" (After
Theory 103)? On this
argument he says that in the same way that "you cannot ask why a
giraffe should do the things it does" (116) one cannot ask why
humanity produces culture, or, in other words, ask, what is the
purpose of culture? In
both cases, however, nature is taken to be a static and unchanging
thing, as if giraffes ever existed outside an ever changing and
evolving material environment which, actually, always does explain
why they should do what they do and not something else, which is, of
course, what Darwin's theory of natural selection is all about. Not
only does Eagleton assume that what makes a giraffe is immanent to
the giraffe outside the material environment in which it must find
food, shelter and other giraffes, thus effectively giving the
giraffe in place of its actual nature a normative cultural identity
(a kind of Platonic essence inscribed in its genes supposedly), but
he also naturalizes culture by treating it as a kind of secretion
that is spontaneously produced by human beings naturally. Eagleton,
following an aesthetic tradition within Western (Hegelian) Marxism
since Adorno, defends "the concept of culture" as "the cultivation
of human powers as ends in themselves" (24) on the argument that not
only is an immanent understanding of culture "resistant" to the law
of value, but, furthermore, that it is embedded in human nature. And
yet, such a self-reflexive concept of culture is not coincident with
humanity as a species; a long period of natural evolution from
bipedalism and the opposable thumb to economic (i.e., conscious)
organization and tool making precedes language and "art," the first
cultural practices which take on the formation of the subject
specifically as their purpose. It is only by suppressing knowledge
of human evolution and the origins of culture in labor that culture
can be made to seem "purposeless" (i.e., something naturally
subjective rather than socially objective). But, not only is culture
always purposeful ("language is practical consciousness," as Marx
and Engels say) because it is economic in essence—it produces a
consciousness of the material process necessary to sustain human
life and helps wrest control over the material world so that humans
are not the slaves of chance and necessity—it also has
cross-purposes that arise, for instance, when short and long term
purposes come into conflict, such as when the needs of immediate
survival conflict with long term sustainability, or, as when culture
serves to "contain" conflicting class interests (ideology).
What is radical about the theory of humanism that Marx advances in
his early writings is how it foresees the need of overcoming
alienation, the negative activity of humanity that consists of
endless "re-appropriation" of our estranged "essence," if we are
ever to become truly human. He argues that "only when we have
superseded this mediation—which is however a necessary
precondition—will positive
humanism, positively originating in itself, come into being" (Early Writings 345). For Marx, human nature is not as Eagleton
imagines, a given, static, and inert thing that "resists" the
outside world. Humanity is a part of nature that if no longer quite
an animal like any other nevertheless remains something less than
fully human, an "instrument of labor" like any other used as a means
to an end, until such time that it acquires "control and conscious
mastery of these powers, which born of the action of men on one
another, have till now overawed and ruled men as powers completely
alien to them" (Marx and Engels,
German Ideology 59).
Without an understanding of what makes the human and why (the mode
of production) it is impossible to make a fundamental critique of
the capitalist exploitation of human labor-power—the estranged labor
that produces and "humanizes" wealth for the capitalist and
impoverishes and "dehumanizes" the worker—and instead things appear
topsy-turvy so that inequality appears to be the result of a "bad"
consciousness—"instrumental reason" (Adorno); "ready-to-hand
thought" (Heidegger); "the spirit of capitalism" (Weber); "carnophallogocentrism"
(Derrida); "privatization of the commons" (Badiou, Negri, Žižek)—to
be re-formed through more ethical discourses, or, in other words,
through spiritual idealization ("learning to live well"). But this
inversion of the material relations into ideology is itself an act
of estranged labor inserted into the division of labor and
represents the product of professional ideologists. In short, it is
another instance of how labor power is exchanged for wages (means of
consumption) rather than to meet human needs as a whole. Ethical
discourses and "spiritual" fixes are commodified ways of
individually learning to come to terms with the exploitation of
labor by capital rather than a way to socially change the world for
the good of all.
It is the domination of capital that subjects labor to meeting
physical needs (wages) and that makes culture into ideology, a
reified activity to rationalize production and normalize the worker
to her own subjection, rather than a material force for social
emancipation from inequality. This is why although Marx argues that
"the nature of the movement [the re-appropriation of estranged human
life] initially depends on whether the actual and
acknowledged life of the
people has its being more in consciousness or in the external world,
in ideal or real life" (Early
Writings 345) he nevertheless maintains that the abolition of
"real" estrangement (private property), as distinct from the
negation of estranged "ideas" (reified thought), "embraces both
aspects" (349) while the contrary is not the case. In other words, the
Hegelian inversion of "substance" as "subject" which negates the
estrangement of ideas from their material basis when they are
considered self-caused (as forms of "thought") is itself an
ideological false consciousness, what Marx calls an "occult
critique" (Economic Manuscripts 130), precisely in the sense
that it does not "embrace" the universal estrangement of labor under
capitalism but only concerns itself with the alienated "labor of
thought" (Marx, Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts 145;
Hegel, Phenomenology 90-1, 128). In the same way the
deconstruction of the human/animal binary inscribed within what
Derrida calls "carnophallogecentric thought" that is effected by
"thinking (the passion) of the animal" as it surfaces bodily in all
inscriptions of knowledge does not "embrace" the material as the
estrangement of human species-being as a whole but only contests the
"ideal" subjection of "thinking" and necessarily reifies the
material as ahistorical "matter" (the body as a certain "experience
of language"). In other words, Derrida simply rehearses how
"thought" too is "other
than itself" (Marx) but does not surface the social forces that
explain why "an inhuman
power rules over everything" (Economic
Manuscripts 110). Without a materialist explanation, thinking
remains alienated and blissfully at home with social inequality. The
critique of "ideal" estrangement (ideological "thought") necessarily
leaves intact the estrangement of human powers as alien powers
embodied in capital which does not change due to changes in
discourse and which "always exceed[s] the fate of signs" (Morton and
Zavarzadeh 7).
Posthumanism is a regime of knowing that represents the material,
which is at root class inequality, as an effect of the immaterial
(knowledge) and advocates for change as a spiritual movement of
ideas (ethics). It for instance argues that at the root of injustice
and inequality is biogenetic "violence" (Derrida,
Animal 25-26) that renders
species undecidable from within and liberates thinking the "passion
of the animal" as the
experience of language ("language about which one could say, even if
it is not in itself 'animal,' that it is not something that the
'animal' could be deprived of"), or what Derrida calls "animal
writing." Humanism on
this view is "speciesism," a mode of policing the "ontological
divide" between the human and non-human (animal) others in
"thought." It seems that
in posthumanist discourses, the more science advances the
understanding of nature and the more life on earth depends on
understanding human species-being as the universal production of the
whole earth ("life-engendering life," Marx), the more impossible it
becomes to know with any certainty what is human, and yet, such
developments actually prove Marx's materialist theory that
"productive life is the life of the species" (Economic
Manuscripts 68). It follows that if in their productive lives
human beings are reduced to the mere maintenance of physical life
while the value of labor is transferred to the commodity then
humanity, and along with it everything else, will appear "other than
itself" and "inhuman."
In place of a materialist theory of species as productive life, the
social is represented in posthumanist cultural theory in an
alienated way, as an inhuman "hauntology" of ghostly traces, a
hybrid creation of "immaterial labor" embodied in transspecies form.
In actuality the immaterial (knowledge) is determined by the
material (class) and the ethical turn of the posthumanities is
nothing more than a justification of the new more profitable forms
of global capital today (e.g.,
e2: The Economies of Being Environmentally Conscious).
The "question of the animal" (Derrida) is part of a broader
"ethical" turn in the humanities that frames issues of injustice and
inequality, which are rooted in class, in cultural terms (knowledge)
that accommodate capitalism as the normal basis of human societies.
On the one hand it shows a concern to extend to animals the
awareness of difference that social movements have brought to
questions of gender, race, and sexuality, and on the other it
represents sensuality and sentimental attachments as an emergent
animal perspective that will transvalue all values (Acampora,
Corporal Compassion: Animal
Ethics and Philosophy of Body), and so one finds Derrida nakedly
communing with his cat and Haraway writing about making love with
her dog through "oral intercourse" (Companion
Species 2-3) as if such sentimental attachments could remake
"reality" (6). In posthumanist writings the agency of change is
"animal writing," what Derrida does when he writes "l'animot"
is to "liberate… animal words" (The
Animal 37) and is an example of what Haraway calls
"dog-writing," a kind of writing that
brings together the human and non-human, the organic and
technological, carbon and silicon, freedom and structure, history
and myth, the rich and the poor, the state and the subject,
diversity and depletion, modernity and postmodernity, and nature and
culture in unexpected ways. (Companion
Species 3-4)
Posthumanist writing consists of telling stories of "co-habitation,
co-evolution, and embodied crossspecies sociality" (Haraway,
Companion Species 4) on the assumption that such "stories are bigger
than ideologies" (17) and determine "the world we might yet live in"
(3) because "reality is an active verb" (6). Central to the
posthumanities is the kind of "animal writing" performed by Derrida
and Haraway as the limit of the radical now, which is currently
consolidating itself into an academic discipline known as "animal
studies." Animal studies is committed to raising awareness of how
humanity has conceived of and related to animals and, as well,
prioritizes the question of how animals experience the world in
non-human ways that are held to provide an "other" awareness
(embodied knowledge) through which to change the ways humans relate
to animals, the world, and each other so as to be more respectful of
differences ("love"). The question of the question of the animal,
however, is not exhausted by such ethical concerns, nor is it
produced immanently within cultural discourses. The ethical turn to
the consideration of the animal is a question because capitalism is
now transforming the biosphere and developing newer forms of
property and class conflict in ways that put the exploitation of
human species-being itself in question and raise awareness of the
necessity of the class struggle for socialism. The "question of the
animal" is the reformist answer to the class inequalities of
capitalism that serves the ruling class which wants a "sustainable"
capitalism with less overt injustice but with class inequality as
the root of the system in exploited labor still intact.
The "question of the animal" is not a questioning of capitalism.
Rather it is against the humanist legitimation of an outdated
("modern," "industrial," "nationalist") capitalism (Ritvo,
The Animal Estate: The English
and Other Creatures in the Victorian Age) and on the side of a
newer posthumanist global capitalism, and so one finds that the new
posthumanist capitalists speak the same posthumanist animal language
of a Derrida or Haraway, as when Joel Salatin, a farm owner,
remarks:
A culture that views a pig as a pile of protoplasmic inanimate
structure to be manipulated by whatever creative design the human
can foist on that critter will probably view individuals within its
community and other cultures in the community of nations with the
same kind of disdain, disrespect and controlling-type mentality. (Food,
Inc.)
Humanist capitalism is a "controlling-type mentality" (carnophallogocentrism;
speciesism); posthumanist capitalism is more "in touch" with the
"commons" (critter life, transspecies, pettism). In other words,
humanist capitalism is "violently" industrial, nationalist, and
monocultural: it penetrates local cultures and causes them to
destroy their forests for export or to hunt species to extinction
for trade, for example. Posthumanist capitalism is more "ethical,"
postindustrial, transnational and multicultural: it cooperates with
local growers to preserve their ecospheres and invents sustainable
forms of agriculture and urbanism and protects wildlife for the
knowledges they may give to future generations. Humanist capitalism
is gray. Posthumanist capitalism is green. But green capitalism like
gray capitalism is a rejection of the red—the emancipatory theory of
labor in which "from each according to their ability, to each
according to his needs" (Marx,
Gotha Programme 531) is the rule and "men not only feel but also
know their oneness with nature" (Engels, Dialectics 181)
because they "produce in accordance with the standard of every
species" (Marx, Economic Manuscripts 69) universally.
The posthumanities advocates the standpoint of the animal as
"resistant" in its opacity to the systematic use of animals for
profit (speciesism) because it values the singularity and difference
of the animal, but global capitalism itself necessitates such an
ethical awareness because of the new forms of property, such as the
genetic engineering of food or the protection of ecospheres for
pharmaceuticals research and development. On the left these new
forms of capital are made into "immaterial" forms of "biopower"
(Foucault, Agamben), or, ironically, in more (neo)marxist terms, as
the privatization of the commons of "general intellect" (Hardt and
Negri, Žižek), as if knowledge were the source of wealth. Biopower
represents the commodification of labor by capital as the result of
a compulsive acquisitive drive for material resources, a
will-to-power to control the "commons" and regulate "life," and not
the class practice of the capitalist to accumulate more
surplus-labor from human labor-power. The displacement of the
material by the immaterial as the underlying logic of the system in
posthumanist theory is an argument for an ethical capitalism that
focuses on the effects of capitalism rather than its cause and in
this way makes individuals seem responsible for its inequalities and
justifies a volunteerism to reform it in localities (pettism) rather
than critique the logic of the class relations.
But capitalism today realizes the most surplus-value precisely
through such ethical practices, through, for instance, the exercise
of "soft power" in "humanitarian aid" missions by US military forces
in response to so-called "natural disasters" as most recently in
Haiti, and the development of
"green alternatives" for industry:
A new poetry of buildings … born of a deeper beauty—not merely sleek
design but rather part of its DNA, ingrained in the materials, its
source, its inner workings, possessing an unseen soul … a building
can do more than stand … it can live and contribute ("Green Apple").
These newer forms of property, unlike the old forms, are represented
as the outcome of immaterial processes (knowledge-work) that are
inherently "clean" (i.e., more efficient, less-wasteful and
therefore ethical or "smart") and therefore "green" (more just). And
yet these forms of property do not lessen but deepen class
exploitation by, for example, using the material resources of the
state to first subsidize their development and then to protect their
monopoly on the new products (as Monsanto does with the patents on
its genetically modified seeds for example or as Pfizer does with
medicine). They commodify the environmental crisis into marketable
products and polarize the social even more between the "haves" and
"have nots." These new forms of exploitation are ideologically
enabled by the new "posthumanist" theories of the material which I
will now turn to consider more closely.
THREE
The canonical figuration of the posthumanities with Derrida at the
center marginalizes theories of posthumanism that regard it as the
dominant ideology of global capitalism, such as Žižek's for
instance. Turning to Žižek's writings one finds a very different way
of making sense of posthumanism according to its "outside."
On Žižek's framing, the posthumanities is really the terrain
in which "we should locate today's struggle between idealism and
materialism" (Parallax View 166) as "class struggle" over the Real ("Repeating
Lenin" n. pag.). The "idealists" are the contemporary
"immaterialists" who reduce phenomena to an absolute plane of
immanence without an outside cause, such as Heidegger (Being),
Derrida (Text), Deleuze (Flows) and Negri (Multitude). Without
accounting for an outside cause, such views produce an
"unconditional voluntarism" (Parallax
View 165) that is at home in the world as it is, following the
dictates of compulsory consumption heedless of the social costs. The
"materialists," conversely, are those who "embed" the "immaterial"
phenomena of culture within its underlying preconditions—capitalism.
Leaving aside for the moment the question of Žižek's understanding
of the outside, class, capitalism, and materialism, how does his
theory lead us to understand the "question of the animal" that is
central to Derrida's formulation of the posthumanities?
Žižek has stated his agreement with Fukuyama's assessment, given in
Our Posthuman Future, of the possibility of the immanent
demise of capitalism by allowing markets deregulated access to the "lifeworld":
we are in danger of losing everything: the threat is that we will be
reduced to abstract subjects devoid of all substantial content,
dispossessed of our symbolic substance, our genetic base heavily
manipulated, vegetating in an unlivable environment. (Tragedy
97)
Despite this agreement, Žižek does not share Fukuyama's idea of
human freedom as cultural competition for status or his global
regulatory fantasies. Žižek is opposed to the essentialist account
of human nature that underlies Fukuyama's writings which figure as
properly human the "struggle for recognition" (culture) as an
extension of the animal struggle for existence (need). According to
Žižek all struggles are "surplus" struggles at the root of which is
the class struggle over surplus-value ("Repeating Lenin"), which
gives form to the cultural struggles beyond the economic struggle
and makes it impossible to ideologically close the gap between "what
is" (inequality) and what "should be" (democracy). Class struggle,
in short, is the "absent cause" (Althusser) at the center of
existence that generates ideological "solutions" but that itself
"eludes symbolization" and explanation. The question for Žižek is
how to figure this gap between the "symbolic" surface conflicts and
the underlying structural contradiction of capitalism in such a way
as to resist its recuperative suturing in the Symbolic edifice of
the culture, a strategy he calls "Bartleby politics" (i.e., "I
prefer not to" repeat the ideology). In other words, his project is
how to "resist" attachment to a "big Other" or "grand narrative" of
history that would seem to "guarantee" a progressive outcome and
thereby promote the usual politics that support the system rather
than provoke a "leap of faith" outside the logic of history.[4] Žižek
thus opposes "traditional history" with "effective history" as in
Foucault's reading of Nietzsche, in "Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,"
which dissolves the ongoing historicity of labor in the "event"-fulness
of ideology (reversal of values). What this does to the concept of
class in Žižek's writings is crucial for understanding their
ideological function.
Žižek turns class into a marker of cultural status. His "class" is
not a matter of "oppressor and oppressed" (Marx and Engels,
"Manifesto," Reader 474) but of symbolic "inclusion and exclusion" from the dominant
culture: "slum dwellers… are 'free' in the double meaning of the
word even more than the classic proletariat ('freed' from all
substantial ties; dwelling in a free space, outside the police
regulations of the state)" ("Ecology" n. pag.). His writings have
become so popular on the left theory market because of the way they
turn class from an economic structure of inequality to an empty
political trope, citing Rancičre's ideological gloss on the
proletariat as "the part of no-part" (Tragedy
99) that whitewashes exploitation and alibis capitalism. His answer
to social injustice and inequality is, as in market criteria, how to
construct an "effective" (which always means popular as in free
market criteria) understanding of class by representing class as
disavowed desire and perverse pleasure rather than alienated labor
and unmet need. In other words, class is posited as a site of
surplus-enjoyment in the culture in which the term is either
invested with negative or affirmative pleasure rather than class as
a matter of who is clothed, fed, housed, educated, healthy, and why.
In this way he makes class into a market identity as in bourgeois
sociology. So, on the one hand, class is a negative Real that eludes
symbolization at the level of culture ("the part of no-part") and,
on the other, it is a positive call to action to struggle against
the privatization of the "commons" (what he calls communism) on the
part of "egalitarian collectives" united by the categorical
imperative that "truth is partial" rather than "objective"
("Repeating Lenin" n. pag.). In terms of ideology, what this
situating of class in relation to culture rather than production
entails is the insistence that behind the symbolic humanization and
naturalization of capitalism as the horizon of struggle ("Ecology"
n. pag.) is an "inhuman" excess ("the materiality of ideology"), a
death-drive implanted in human beings by the market that produces a
"surplus-pleasure" to be found both in the sacrifice of one's normal
identity as a consumer and symbolic rebirth as an ethical subject.
For Žižek, the contemporary represents the moment when the inhuman
drive of capitalism that enslaves the individual to the loop of
desire and prioritizes it before the social good is extended into
the symbolic (the cultural sphere), which puts it up for
contestation and resignification in ways that may challenge the
consumerism and technocratic reason of the dominant ideology such as
to make possible a truly authentic ethical act to commit oneself to
the overthrow of capitalism.
Clearly, in Žižek's terms Haraway's "transspecies" and Derrida's "l'animot"
are as equally problematic as Fukuyama's defense of the human
because they all ideologically cover over a real contradiction
between the inside (capitalism) and the outside (communism). They
all reduce the class struggle, which structures culture, to the
terms of the cultural as a plane of immanence in which (class)
antagonism is normalized as the self-difference within class (e.g.,
J.K. Gibson-Graham, Class and Its Others), and disappear the
struggle between classes over the "inhuman" social Real (the
"commons"). And yet Žižek's understanding of the outside is also not
outside but inside, what he calls the ethical Act, or, following
Badiou, "fidelity to the event" or the "idea of communism" (i.e.,
defense of the commons), that makes class into a marker of different
lifestyles: the "working class" is thus a plurality of market
identities that consists of "intellectual laborers, the old manual
working class, and the outcasts" each with their own "identity
politics" ("multiculturalism"/"populist fundamentalism"/"gangs")
formed in response to the state "privatization" that "desubstantializes"
the "commons" (the "general intellect"
Tragedy 147) and thus makes them "free … to invent some mode of
being-together" ("Ecology" n. pag.).
Žižek's opposition to the humanism of "state philosophy," which he
locates both in the
Fukuyamian attempt to delimit a properly human sphere of ethics from
an encroaching "inhuman" otherness and in the postmodern Left who
fetishize a sublime otherness (pettism), is finally not so radical
because he represents capitalism as an "inhuman" drive that
nullifies the revolutionary agency of the proletariat, which is the
material, not symbolic, critique of everything existing, and "the
real movement which
abolishes the present state of things" (Marx and Engels,
The German Ideology 57)
because of its centrality to capitalism. Žižek rejects what he calls
the "old" and "naďve" theory of surplus-value of Marx and in place
of Marx's class theory of culture puts his own cultural theory of
class as a matter of who is included/excluded from the hegemonic
form of "enjoyment" ("Monstrosity of Christ" n. pag.). He claims
that the proletariat no longer exists as the mass of workers
exploited at the point of production and that Marx's theory of value
as the exploitation of labor is out of date (Tragedy
145) because there is no more exploitation now that knowledge is the
source of value ("general intellect") and profit is not made from
surplus-labor but "rent" (of copyrighted software for example).[5]
Leaving aside that what he describes is actually double
profit—not only does the capitalist own the labor embodied in the
commodity but also the wages to access it through monopoly control
of the market—in place of the proletariat as "the
real movement which
abolishes the present state of things," Žižek instead places those
he calls "toxic subjects," "outcasts," or "slum dwellers" on the
grounds that they are excluded from authentic recognition by the
culture for what is in effect, on his reading, their cynical
non-affirmative consumption, which he romanticizes as "Bartleby
politics" ("Learn to Live Without Masters" n. pag.). Žižek rewrites
"class" in cultural terms as those who are not "included" in the
"symbolic social substance" (i.e. "commons," "general intellect")
and whose exclusion becomes its own source of pleasure: "'freed'
from all substantial ties… they have to invent some mode of
being-together" ("Ecology" n. pag.). In Žižek's theory, in contrast
to classical Marxist theory, "toxic subjects" are not understood as
subjects of history whose agency is material and the effect of the
structure of capitalism that exploits them, as in classical Marxist
theory. Instead, they are subjects understood as "free agents,"
conscientious objectors to the class war between exploiters and
exploited, who act spontaneously in the market as counter-hegemonic
ethical agents and who never question the exploitation of labor by
capital at the root of capitalism but simply question its
ideological supremacy because they feel alienated from it. In short,
they are good bourgeois subjects who see themselves as free
individuals, as in bourgeois ideology. Capital of course depends on
these "free subjects" to normalize the exchange of labor for wages
as a relation that is freely entered into and to mystify the
exploitation of labor by capital.
For all his denouncing of the "resistance" politics (Laclau, Butler,
Critchley) which fundamentally accepts capitalism as the silent and
unquestioned "background," Žižek's notion of politics is finally no
different. It amounts to resisting the privatization of the
"commons," which in his writings means resisting the "private"
(instrumental) use of reason by the State (citing Kant), so that the
"immediate universal" substance ("general intellect") may display
itself unhindered, without representation and regulation, as a
screen on which to project more "authentic" images of
surplus-enjoyment. In short, he wants a de-regulated symbolic
economy, or, more commonly, freedom of speech. His insistence on the
"materiality of ideology" as the limit of the possible is done so as
to figure movement to the outside in libertarian terms, as simply
opting out ("I prefer not to") or "demanding the impossible" (as in
the old '68 slogan). It
is the lack of a materialist theory of value that leads Žižek, like
Negri and Hardt, into spiritualism and voluntarism as a political
strategy and to the embrace of bourgeois ideology; as when he claims
that Saint Paul is a true Leninist (Puppet 9) for such moral
platitudes as that radical change begins as "a change in you"
("Interview" 36). Žižek fetishizes the "encounter with the Real" as
identification with that which is not yet culturally "schematized"
and thereby holds out the hope of an alternative schematization;
"When the normal run of things is traumatically interrupted the
field is opened up for discursive ideological competition" (Tragedy
17). What is ruled out by such an adventurist cultural politics
of the spectacle is the advancement of revolutionary politics based
on the struggle over material resources and meeting people's needs.[6
Žižek "surpasses" Negri-Hardt on the transpatriotic Left by saying
that it is those who are excluded from the commons of "general
intellect" that are revolutionary not those who participate in it by
producing new ideas of sociality (Tragedy 39-41). These
"outcasts" are the ones whose consumption does not add value—because
it does not affirm the political ideology of ethical capitalism
through which products are marketed today—and therefore does not
support the "new" cultural capitalism which unlike the "old"
capitalism is based not on surplus-labor but surplus-pleasure. By
withholding their affirmation they practice a cynical consumption
that then marks them symbolically for exclusion (as "toxic
subjects," "outcasts," "terrorists," etc.). This is of course a
meta-cynical theory which finds spontaneously in the market a
disaffected lifestyle that offers a ready-made model of revolution
without the need for theory ("I prefer not to") and the hard task of
building a revolutionary party. But, as Lenin says, "without
revolutionary theory there can be no revolutionary movement" (What Is To Be Done? 25).
Žižek is playing with the concrete surfaces of meaning in culture
which on his own terms is a way to "privatize the commons" and
justify an ethical capitalism. The value Žižek adds to the "general
intellect" is the idea that cynical (non-affirmative) consumption
spontaneously undermines capitalism, an idea which simply makes its
peace with the ongoing exploitation of labor embodied in the
commodity. The "idea of communism" he defends (following Badiou) is
a romantic sublime indebted to Heidegger's ethos of "letting being
be" which, like the "refusal of work" doctrine of the autonomist
marxists, is a theology of crisis in which the "weak" are
represented as "strong in spirit" and in which we see the
intellectuals abandon their social duty to educate the laboring
masses (the exploited) in their struggle against the exploiter
(capital) by becoming cheerleaders for whatever is popular at the
time. On this logic "the poor are actually extraordinarily wealthy"
(Hardt and Negri, Multitude 131) because "despite the myriad mechanisms of hierarchy
and subordination" they are "creative" and "express an enormous
power of life" (129), or, in Žižek's terms, "'freed' from all
substantial ties" they are "'free'… to invent some mode of
being-together" ("Ecology" n. pag.). Unlike Hardt, Negri and
Starbucks, however, Žižek does not insist that spiritual values
necessarily lead to a good society because there are no guarantees
that it will (now that history has been "desubstantialized"), and it
may just as well strengthen the state. When one considers the role
of the state in the "authoritarian capitalism" he locates in China,
the normalization of which he sees as inevitable, his passionate
embrace of "the Cross of the postrevolutionary present" (Parallax
View 5) as an example of how the "lowest" is the "highest"
(Hegel's "infinite judgment") is particularly cynical. Žižek's
messianic embrace of the oppressed is, in other words, conditional
upon their remaining oppressed. Hence all the awkward and
oft-repeated Gulag jokes at the expense of his "enemies" to lighten
things up, as if to say, "I am not really serious, I would not take
power and incarcerate and indoctrinate you—like
them." But the jokes have a serious message; they signal the
cynical belief in an eternal capitalism and are a mark of class
belonging among those who are engrossed in inventing pleasures above
and beyond the struggle over material need, which they are allowed
to enjoy because they justify consuming the labor of the other.
Žižek finds in the indirect style of deconstruction in which
materiality is reduced to textual mediations a hidden belief in
substantial "reality" that indicates its silent complicity with the
dominant ideology, what he calls "objective belief" (On Belief).
Objective belief, for Žižek, functions by taking the subject out of
the picture as if the Real simply exists without the active
participation of subjects who normalize it precisely by disavowing
the complicity of their attempts to ameliorate things through such
mechanisms as activism, charity, and ethical consumption, which
support the status quo. Žižek embraces the "monstrosity of Christ"
and "Bartleby politics" as marginalized figures of non-participation
in the dominant ideology who embody the self-sacrificing ideals of
egalitarian collectivity by "doing nothing" but "thinking" during
moments of social crisis. But how effective is this
counter-strategy? Žižek reverses Marx's eleventh thesis when he
argues that "the first task today is precisely not to succumb to the
temptation to act… but to question the hegemonic" ("Repeating Lenin"
n. pag.). In doing so, he leaves intact the ideological notion that
the eleventh thesis is the formula for an ethical calling (i.e.,
Badiou's "fidelity to the Event"). By contrast, Marx's argument that
philosophers having already interpreted the world while the point is
to change it is not an ethical call to spontaneous activism but a
materialist guide for actions based on the recognition that "it is
not the consciousness of men that determines their existence, but
their social existence that determines their consciousness" (Marx,
Contribution 21). In other words, Marx is not posing the question of
whether one should choose to think or act, as Žižek imagines, but
revealing the complicity of thought in social praxis. Žižek's view
is exactly the opposite: it invites one to imagine that theory and
practice are separate self-enclosed activities it is possible to
choose between and by choosing "thinking" and rejecting ideology ("I
prefer not to") silently assumes that consciousness determines
social existence. In other words, he apparently believes that by
"merely combating the phrases of this world" (Marx and Engels,
The German Ideology 36) he
is changing it, or as he puts it, "When the normal run of things is
traumatically interrupted the field is opened up for discursive
ideological competition" (Tragedy
17). Žižek's "dialectical materialism" is really a version of
Hegel's objective idealism in which ideas determine the material,
which is why he rejects ideology critique as "a reduction of the
higher intellectual content to its lower economic… cause" (Parallax
View ix) for immanent critique which aims at "the inherent
decentering of the interpreted text" by surfacing "its 'unthought'…
disavowed presuppositions and consequences" (ix). Thinking the
unthought and disavowed (i.e., encountering the traumatic Real that
contradicts ideology in daily life) is represented by Žižek as more
important than surfacing the determination of thought in the social
totality (class). In short, this substitutes ideological inversion
for a materialist critique that uncovers the economic forces that
structure the totality as a guide to praxis. His understanding of
"class" as inclusion/exclusion in the "social substance of ideology"
is itself a dissimulation of class privilege in that it assumes the
world is shaped by ideas, the material by the immaterial, as in all
bourgeois ideology.
What people think and believe, however, whether it is the dominant
ideology or revolutionary ideas, are always a reflection of the
class relations that determine the limits of the possible. If the
world appears determined by ideology this is simply a result of the
fact that in practice labor is itself "estranged" at the point of
production and what appears to be an equal and fair exchange of
labor for wages is in actuality the exploitative extraction of
surplus-labor from the worker by the capitalist, which subordinates
labor to capital. The objective appearance of the exchange of labor
for wages in the market is itself already ideological and disguises
the class inequality between capital and labor without the need of
any extra cultural reinforcement (i.e., surplus-pleasure). Moreover,
this objective ideology, which is daily reproduced in material
practice, can only be penetrated by Marx's labor theory of value,
which explains that what the worker sells to the capitalist is not
her labor (a commodity like any other) but her labor-power—a
"special commodity" that produces more value as it is consumed
(Marx, Capital 270). Žižek's "surplus" theory of ideology in which ideology
is made into a phantom value, a surplus-pleasure beyond normal
pleasure, which he places as the object (a)
of all struggles, does what bourgeois ideology has always done which
is to disguise the outright theft of labor-power by the capitalist,
not in the everyday surfaces of consumption but daily at the point
of production, in the "working day" (Marx,
Capital 340-411).
For Žižek, species-being (i.e., Marx's explanation of "life
activity," "productive life," "life-engendering life"), which
explains labor as the source of value, is a piece of New Age-y
mysticism ("cosmic awareness" or "holistic immersion"
Tragedy 94) that must be dismissed because "nature doesn't exist,"
"there is no Evolution," and "one should thus learn to accept the
utter groundlessness of our existence" ("Ecology" n. pag.). In this
he is echoing Badiou who rejects any "figure which makes man into a
species" (The Century 174)
on the grounds that to do so reduces politics to the mere
maintenance of animal life as in the biopolitics of "state
philosophy."
Species-being is thus posited as a "new opium of the masses" through
which late capitalism manages its contradictions by adopting a
"co-operative" ontology (humanist speciesism). On this view,
species-being (labor) is a socialist ideology that has been
incorporated into the maintenance of capitalism and what is really
radical is commitment to the "idea of communism," not as the
movement of history, but as a categorical imperative that "truth is
partial" and cannot be grounded in any "big Other" because now that
the "commons" has been privatized "substance is subject," as Hegel
thought, and we are "free… to invent some mode of being-together"
("Ecology" n. pag.). On Žižek's view, class is thus a "sublime
object" of ideology, with all of its religious aroma, rather than
the material basis of what exists. Desire and not need is at the
center of the social. Desire, however, not as human but as inhuman.
It is not, in other words, desire as it arises out of the social
relations through which men and women meet their needs, but desire
as a trope to mark the fact that his analytics remains immanent to
the dominant ideology of compulsory consumption (the law of
enjoyment). Desire is "inhuman" because Žižek considers it a
"compulsive" force that negates the autonomy of the ego (will,
reason, etc.), pace Freud ("death drive"). Yet in this way "desire"
is de-humanized—it is not understood as emerging from the social
relations—and becomes in fact an ideology or "false consciousness":
a way to "imagine… false or seeming motive forces" in place of "the
real motive forces" that compel individuals (Engels, "Letters on
Historical Materialism" 766). In short, Žižek's notion of death
drive as the inhuman compulsion of desire is simply a mystification
of "the silent compulsion of economic relations" (Marx,
Capital 899). It is
libidinal economy masquerading as political economy in the attempt
to imagine a posthumanist reversal of values in which the human
being embodies the "passion of the animal" (Derrida), which is a
trope that mystifies the actual reduction of humans by capital to
bare animal existence.
Because capitalism has clearly become destructive in its effects and
cannot meet the needs of the masses (the primary producers of
wealth) the dominant ideology of bourgeois society has become
posthumanist and inscribes the notions that; (1) the human is not a
unique and singular being but a shifting construct made from out of
spectral values, affects, desires, etc. that emerges from the
"ontological divide" in Western discourse erected between the
"human" and "non-human" in culture; (2) culture as a realm of values
cannot be considered distinct from nature as "not culture" and
"value-less" because such distinctions are always "embodied": value
hierarchies mark subjects by inhabiting the "matter" of bodies and
are always "lived" by (human, non-human, posthuman) individuals.
What the first premise denies is that labor (human species-being) is
the unique and singular source of value because it is only due to
social labor that humans have the special capacity to know and
transform nature as a whole, not only in accordance with human needs
but also the needs of nature. This quality of human laboring
activity being "life-engendering life" (Marx) and not merely a
life-maintaining activity is what makes humans not simply a species
like any other but also one whose form of activity takes
historically specific forms ("modes of production"). It also
explains why labor in its current form, as the commodity whose
consumption in the production process increases value beyond its
immediate use, is a transitional and historical form of
species-life. Making the human a spectral category whose internal
displacements reveal the impossibility of positive and reliable
knowledge of the real is to disappear the surplus-value extracted
from human labor that makes all value in commodity culture (even the
value of so-called "natural resources" which cannot be utilized
without the application of labor).
The second premise erases the distinction between culture and nature
through the category of "embodiment"—as in Foucault's "materialism
of the incorporeal" in which knowledge is always an effect of how
power inscribes bodies. In doing so, this premise further assumes
that "matter" is a "thing" (body). But while what is material is
always bound up with a conception of value such a conception is
itself always valued relative to the development of the forces of
production. If today, for instance, it is "bodies that matter"
(Butler, Grosz) rather than "textuality" (Barthes, Derrida, De Man),
it is not simply the result of an ethical turn but because textual
materialism appears outdated in the transnational cyber-economy of
cell phones, software, DVDs, social networking, and Web 2.0. The
international language of the televisual economy, what one cultural
critic calls the "iconomy" (Smith), is visual literacy (just look at
international airport signage or IKEA instructions), and, as any
global blockbuster film will show (e.g.,
Avatar), visual literacy
must be discursively formulaic and appeal to the immediacy of the
senses (embodiment) in order to realize a profit. Embodiment, the
matter of the body as the limit-text of thinking materiality in
posthumanist cultural theory, is valued now because it reflects in
ideology the new global property forms developed to commodify the
environmental crisis by re-tooling industry through what is being
called "sustainable design" on the grounds that with existing
technologies it is possible to reduce the human footprint by 90% (The
11th Hour). On
this market logic, "All of life is actually a design project today"
and what matters most is thus the sensual "interface" between the
consumer and the new products (Bruce Mau as qtd. in The 11th
Hour). In short, the notion of matter changes not simply because
of a cultural change in values but because of changes in the mode of
production and the forms of property.[7]
The material is a social relation not a "thing." In other words,
what is material is the structure of need, which is inscribed in the
relation between wage labor and capital; labor at a certain level of
historical development is embodied in private property (capital) to
which there corresponds an ideological form of consciousness. In
this sense, the material is not simply "matter"—whether conceived as
"sensuous" "thingness," or, as in the posthumanist logic as the
embodiment of knowledge, codes, affects, and so forth. Making the
limit of the material the matter of bodies is really just a way to
make reliable knowledge of these material relations—and their
limits—conceptually unattainable by defining the material in terms
of its opacity to consciousness (the unfathomable secret core of
matter that Kant called the "thing-in-itself") and thereby
authorizing lived experience as the limit-text of knowing. However,
"'lived' experience is not a
given… but the spontaneous 'lived experience' of ideology in its
peculiar relationship to the real" (Althusser 223). More
specifically, lived experience is the logic of consumption that
serves big business by encouraging "alternative" consumption in the
time of overproduction.
Today materialism is being discussed in terms of its effects at the
level of consciousness—that is, as "materialism of the incorporeal"
(Foucault) or the "materiality of ideology" (Žižek)—on the
assumption that the material is the "matter" perceived by the
senses, behind which lies the "immaterial" ideas that determine its
form. However, what is being called "immaterial" and "emotional
labor" and made into the form-giving agency that Hardt and Negri
call the "multitude" and Žižek calls the "commons" is simply a trope
for that moment of production in which the object of labor is the
subject herself that has always been a part of the labor process now
as ever. This is, by the way, why Hardt and Negri can attribute this
reflexive idea to Marx by citing his phrase, "l'homme
produit l'homme" (Commonwealth
136). This simply means that labor is a dialectical activity.
Labor, in other words, is not a "one-sided" working upon things but
an "all-sided" activity that produces the subject as well as the
object. Furthermore, it is a social process of production that is
undertaken in accordance with material necessity: "Production not
only supplies a material for the need, but it also supplies a need
for the material... [it] not only creates an object for the subject,
but also a subject for the object... Production thus creates the
consumer" (Marx, Grundrisse 92). Obviously, calling the
production of subjectivity "immaterial" simply maintains an
ideological distinction between mental and manual labor, one that
presupposes an empiricist understanding of the material as matter.
In this matterist view, labor is defined by the type of "thing" it
produces and hence "immaterial" when the "thing" produced is
subjectivity or affective attachments ("emotional labor" or
services). When Hardt and Negri say that they agree with Marx that
"humans produce and humans are produced" (136) but follow Foucault
in rejecting Marx's "humanism" (136) and, moreover, when they reject
Marx's dialectical critique for Kant's transcendental critique (Commonwealth 6), this is their way of denying that labor is more
than a "thing"—it is what Marx calls species-being ("life
activity, productive life").
Labor (species-being, life activity, productive life) is the
structure of necessity that explains the seemingly disparate and
apparently concrete as an effect of the social transformation of
nature. Labor is the determinate relation behind any explanation of
the world we see and it can only be ignored in the imaginary: What
is "imagined" however is also explained by labor. In short, labor is
dialectical—what is usually "ascribed to the mind," or, "to the
development and activity of the brain," is in actuality a product of
the "idealistic world outlook" which has emerged and is maintained
due to advances in labor from simple and straightforward practices
to more complex and opaque combinations (Engels,
Dialectics 178). Marx's concept of species being is root knowledge
for uncovering the "part played by labor" in the so-called "posthumanist"
culture because "labor is the unique and singular source of value"
that is being "resignified" in "imaginative" ways to reform
capitalism in localities but that yet explains contemporary culture
in all its forms as alienated and exploited labor demanding
transformation of the totality.
Badiou's "formalized in-humanism" (178) for instance, takes the
"inhuman" effects of social praxis under the existing capitalist
relations of production as the basis upon which to adopt Foucault's
anti-humanism against the "anthropology" of Marx: "the man of
inhuman beginning, who installs his thought in what happens and
abides in the discontinuity of this arrival" (174). What is regarded
as human on these terms is always the projection of agency onto the
past, a retroactive application of identity into the contingent
events, forces, and wills that make up history, following
Nietzsche's reversal of causality from an objective determination
into an affective one (Will To
Power 293-300). Yet, what is being marked as "inhuman" here, the
"eventfulness" of history, is in actuality a testimony to the
materiality of labor, and not of discontinuity. The "lag" between
"what happens" and how it is "thought" is explained not by
"discontinuity" but by the process of the material causation of
thought: "Mankind... inevitably sets itself only such tasks as it is
able to solve, since closer examination will always show that the
problem itself arises only when the material conditions for its
solution are already present or at least in the course of formation"
(Marx, "Preface to the Critique of Political Economy" 21). What is
being called "in-human" is actually the product of human labor at a
certain point of historical development in which the "needs of
nature" (Marx) are currently being ignored because of the immediate
imperative to profit a few from the exploitation of human
labor-power. In other words, thinking humanity as an "in-human"
projection is simply to re-turn the human to a figure of free
thinking (the messianic) and to disappear the labor relations that
always shape thinking. What is taking place in posthumanist cultural
theory are more stories that perform in their folds a willful
ignorance about labor, the universal species-being that is alone the
agent of history.
FOUR
The "question of the animal" in the posthumanities is a sign of a
deep cynicism toward global explanations and a compulsive naďveté, a
making do with less so as to feel at home in the world as part of
the "vulnerable" "pathos" of the commons—"the nonpower at the heart
of power," "the passion of the animal." It codifies in theory the
species-friendly consumer practices of the upper middle class that
justifies capital investments in environmental solutions for
industry as heralding a green capitalism. Behind it there is
rehearsed a series of assumptions that suggest the world is a harsh
dehumanized place from which springs the need for human contact but
as no one can be trusted without consensus as to the social good,
one must connect with the animal(s) as a way back to "commonality"
with nature as well as with human others.[8] With one's pet—which,
arguably, all animals are today in the sense that their existence
depends on human species-being (labor)—one comes to a subtle
communion with whatever nature and the world looks new. Its
alienated appearance is transformed from a digital waste land bereft
of life into a cooperative organism in a constant flux of becoming.
What has been wasted, such is the messianic promise, will be
recycled and made anew. Exploitation is the past and has been
replaced by caring, service, and cooperation. This series of
ideological assumptions is found across the cultural spectrum from
the discourses of "high theory" (Derrida) to "popular culture"
(e.g., films such as Wendy and
Lucy, Rise of the Planet of the Apes, and Etienne!).
Take the "indie" film Wendy
and Lucy (2008) for instance. The "meaning" of the film cannot
be separated from its "poetics."
The minimal dialogue, the low-fi sound (the humming
soundtrack) and image production values, the trendy androgyny of its
main character (Michelle Williams), her DIY lifestyle as she crosses
the northwest looking for work, hipster superstar Will Oldham's
cameo appearance as a crusty anarcho-punk (Icky),... are all
strategically designed to signal to the audience the "alternative"
credentials of the film in relation to mainstream commercial
film-making—it is not an "industry" film but a postindustrial film
with "heart." The story as well is also concerned to show how
alternative forms of culture (lifestyles) emerge from out of
impoverished conditions, not only across cultural lines (as with
Wendy's friendship with the security guard), but across species as
well.
Wendy and her dog Lucy are driving from Indiana, where she had been
living with her sister Deb and Deb's boyfriend Dan, to Alaska
because she's heard "they need people" to work. The story picks up
with Wendy and Lucy as they are crossing Oregon and is mainly about
their separation when Wendy is arrested for shoplifting dog food.
The fact that Wendy has money to purchase the dog food is an ironic
emphasis of the point made by the store employee who aggressively
detains her and insists she be made an "example" of by having her
arrested: "if a person can't afford dog food, they shouldn't have a
dog." On this logic
Wendy's attachment to Lucy must submit to a coldly dispassionate
cost-benefit analysis so as to avoid transgressing the logic of
profit. Wendy's evident anxiety throughout the film to be reunited
with Lucy is partially to be explained no doubt by her own guilty
complicity with this common-sense morality: If she valued Lucy so
much why did she not just pay for the dog food?
The film deploys a series of binary oppositions that
underline the same point that, on the one hand, the logic of the
market and authentic feelings are antithetical but, on the other,
the authenticity of feelings can only be expressed through market
transactions. Icky, the crust punk who tells the story of how he
recklessly destroyed an expensive piece of machinery working in the
Alaskan fisheries, represents the inhuman other who has rejected the
market while other (equally unattractive) characters in the film are
meant to represent those whom the market has failed (e.g., the
cyborgian figure in the wheelchair who is briefly glimpsed while the
Walgreens guard muses in voiceover about how people "waste" their
days since the mill closed).
Not only is Wendy alienated from Deb and Dan—who, despite the fact
that she has not asked for anything and only wants some expression
of kindness and sympathy, can only repeat that they cannot help her
when in emotional desperation she calls them long distance—but Wendy
is also shown to be alienated from her peers, both the cluelessly
lawless crust punks she encounters on her travels, as well as the
zealously lawful store employee who busts her. The social alienation
that is depicted—where the logic of the market disrupts a shared
sense of common humanity and empathy with others—has the effect of
an inversion that humanizes Lucy the dog while making pet ownership
seem like a radically transgressive act. Wendy's ownership of Lucy,
the logic of the film suggests, represents "caring" for the other at
a time when it has become socially impossible for people to care for
each other. Significantly, the only people Wendy is able to talk to
in non-instrumental terms are those who show feelings for Lucy—the
crust punk girl and the Walgreens security guard—suggesting that
more important than socio-political divisions, such as between Law
(protection of property) and Anarchy (disregard for property), is
the moral divide between those who feel a connection with animals
and those who do not. It is perhaps to the same point that work in a
fishery in Alaska seems to be the only industrial work left in
America. In other words, "they need people" in Alaska… to kill
animals. In short, the problem with capitalism is alienation from
others and the natural world, a problem that the film suggests can
be fixed by bonding with (by personally owning) animals at a time
when capital is indifferent to the social costs it inflicts and
people are made redundant and no longer able to care for themselves.
The fact that Wendy leaves Lucy with a foster home also suggests,
however, that caring for the other and private ownership are
synonymous and can yet provide a way to compensate for the brutal
violation of shared feelings, which is due after all to Wendy's
personal lack of resources. Even though Wendy and Lucy both cry when
separating viewer's are reassured it is what is best for Lucy and
that Wendy is acting like a mature and responsible person by
sacrificing her only friendship to the logic of the market. The
viewer is then ideologically reconciled to submitting to
exploitation by being reassured that in future Wendy will assume
greater personal responsibly so as to avoid such heart-wrenching
separations from her loved ones.
Wendy and Lucy is a "posthumanist"
text for two reasons: firstly, it represents society as
"dehumanized" and the dehumanization as the outcome of industrial
production, and, secondly, it proposes as a solution to the
spiritual deadening of humanity forming emotional attachments with
non-human creatures (pettism). Pettism, in actuality, is the
ideology of a green capitalism in which the biggest profits stand to
be made from retro-fitting industry to be more environmentally
sustainable. Furthermore, it reinforces the division of labor,
between "hi-" and "lo-tech" workers for example, through the
inculcation of more up-to-date cultural values—treating animals
humanely as life companions becomes a sign of ethical distinction.
What is elided by such a lifestyle politics of course is how class
inequality underlies values.
Wendy and Lucy is a "post-apocalyptic"
tale in which human beings have lost all semblance of "humanity" and
can no longer form connections with others and is in this way
similar to the other "post-apocalyptic" tales that are currently on
the market.[9] In The
Road the ultimate expression of inhumanity is to be treated like
so much meat by those who have reverted to cannibalism.
Significantly, in the film based on the book, the last scene in
which The Boy is united with The Family on the beach assures the
audience as to the humanity of these characters by a series of
close-ups that move from the parents to the children and, lastly,
their dog. What this image of the dog represents of course is that
these post-human characters are truly human (they "carry the fire"
in the parlance of The Boy) because not only do they not treat
people like animals (for food) but they treat animals humanely as
equals, despite being reduced to absolute poverty themselves.
Similarly, Wendy's abandonment of Lucy to a foster home that can
provide for her because she is too poor to do so herself is also
meant to signal her humanity in a de-humanized world (the "strength
of the weak," "the passion of the animal"). Unlike
The Road, however, in
which the source of the posthumanist "apocalypse" is not directly
represented or explained,
Wendy and Lucy does, in a way, give a "crisis diagnosis" (Benhabib
109) of the dehumanization of the social in its depiction of human
beings as having lost control of technology.
The point of Icky's story about wrecking an expensive piece of
machinery at work while on drugs is that he was unable to stop the
machine; the drawn out details and seemingly pointless repetition of
Wendy's arrest are clearly shown to be due to the police not having
mastered their technology; the de-industrialization of the town is
shown to be producing "monsters" (e.g., the "creepy" man in the
woods, the "mutant" wheelchair figure); and the playful way the film
doubles the lo-fi music of the soundtrack (which seems to represent
Wendy humming a tune in her head) in the digitized muzak of the
grocery store in which she is arrested suggests that the most
intimate and authentic part of a person is really a scripted reflex
of mass consumer culture. In these ways the film argues that the
dehumanization of the social is due to the negation of the human by
technology and it represents humans as having lost control of the
machine which now controls them.
However, in its "crisis diagnosis" that technological dehumanization
is at the root of the social crisis
Wendy and Lucy also makes
a material explanation impossible and proposes instead a spiritual
solution to the crisis ("pettism") that goes along with an
"alternative" consumerist ideology.[10] But, as Engels' makes clear in "The Part Played by Labour in
the Transition From Ape to Man," the destructiveness of capitalism
on the environment is not primarily a problem with technology or a
technological problem. Primarily it is a problem with the use of
technology by capital for the short-term realization of profit in
the context of market competition which does not concern itself with
the long-term results to the biosphere (the "metabolism" between
labor and nature in Marx's terms). By ascribing the social crisis to
a loss of humanity
caused by technology, Wendy
and Lucy blocks awareness of the social basis (the class
arrangements) that explains why technology under capitalism is not
an emancipatory but an enslaving and destructive force in the long
run and, thus, why the working class alone is the agent of history
in a material position and with a material interest to abolish
capitalism.
The film reifies the effects of the exploitation of labor by
capital, by instead representing technology as the material base,
and in this way produces a spiritual interpretation of technology
(it is "dehumanizing") for which there is a false spiritual solution
(pettism) that stimulates further consumption (ownership of
"companion" animals). The film's occulting of labor, however, is the
primary means for immunizing capitalism from social critique and
thus blocks changing it. The posthumanist critique of dehumanization
is itself dehumanizing because it understands the social as
"immaterial" at root rather than material—it is the disappearance of
jobs and the end of meaningful work in the post-industrial economy
rather than the commodification of labor in the production process
that explains the existing social relations. In actuality, the "loss
of control" over technology that is supposed to explain the
posthumanist world as a world of immaterial production is really a
local effect of exploited and estranged labor in general. Even the
idea that emotionally connecting with pets represents the basis of
an alternative immaterial economy forgets that dogs are embodied
labor.[11] It is because labor has been socialized and the
world is "more and more splitting up into two great hostile camps,
into two great classes directly facing each other: Bourgeoisie and
Proletariat" (Marx and Engels, Reader 474), while control of the production process is privatized in
the hands of a few to make profit from labor, that industry is
enslaving humanity on a self-destructive course. The solution begins
with producing awareness of the social power of labor to transform
the existing in accordance with human needs, which includes
understanding the needs of the biosphere as a whole, and engaging in
a critique of the "immaterial" posthumanist ideology that negates
labor in the cultural imaginary. Pettism, rather than representing a
realistic solution for immaterial times, actually reflects a
bourgeois relation with animals that negates in the imaginary the
labor relations that shape the human interaction with non-human
nature. It is the distortion of needs by private property that
reduces animals to food for the "all too human" masses on the one
side and "companions" for the privileged "posthumanists" on the
other who because their needs have already been met through the
labor of the other are free to "feel" the "passion of the animal."
The "question of the animal" is a desire-al and affective form of
knowing (embodied knowledge) that immunizes global capitalism from
critique by representing its alternative as a new transspecies
commons (pettism). But, the "passion of the animal" always leads to
one conclusion: "The real difference between cat-lovers and
dog-lovers has nothing to do with income, education or habits of
work. It is… a matter of morals" (Fernández-Armesto n. pag.). It
presents class inequality as affective cultural differences
(Derrida, A Taste for the
Secret) and considers it is thereby respecting animal
difference, but it actually thus insures the continued
production/use of animals for profit which will only end when
production is carried out in accordance with meeting human needs,
which includes the needs of nature as Engels says, rather than the
exchange of labor for wages.
The most radical means of thinking the existence that we share with
animals is not some "abyssal" knowing beyond knowing ("passion")
ourselves as sublimely posthumanist animal-others, but knowing the
root of our species-being which "both in man and in animals,
consists physically in the fact that man (like the animal) lives on
organic nature" (Marx Economic Manuscripts 67). As Marx argues, a "species-character is
contained in the character of its life activity"—which for humans is
not only a matter of how physical existence demands labor in the
transformation of inorganic nature "in the form of food, heating,
clothes, a dwelling, etc.," but also, as well, requires "spiritual
nourishment" that must be realized through the processing of
"plants, animals, stones, air, light, etc." by "human consciousness"
into "objects of natural science [and] objects of art" (67). It is
only in knowing species-being in these terms that we become aware of
our relation with the natural world and thus are in a position to
live in a non-destructive relation to the environment as well as
other species. As Engels explains, the more "men not only feel but
also know their oneness with nature… the more impossible will become
the senseless and unnatural idea of a contrast between mind and
matter, man and nature, soul and body" and humanity will be in "a
position to realize, and hence to control, also the more remote
natural consequences of at least our day-to-day production
activities" (Dialectics 181).
As Marx explained, it is the activity of labor that distinguishes
the human species from all others and "makes all nature his
inorganic body" (67) because the "life activity" of the human
species is "universal" ("life-engendering life"):
The life of the species, both in man and in animals, consists
physically in the fact that man (like the animal) lives on organic
nature; and the more universal man (or the animal) is, the more
universal is the sphere of inorganic nature on which he lives. (Economic
Manuscripts 67)
According to the posthumanist Left, to produce a critique-al
knowledge of production as species-being can only be "speciesism"
that perpetuates a violence on the other ("carnophallogocentrism").
Yet, without such a concept what cannot be explained is the material
basis that underlies and connects humanity with the rest of nature
nor, therefore, "how to produce in accordance with the standard of
every species" (Marx, Economic
Manuscripts 69) given that humans produce universally by
transforming all of nature into an "inorganic body" and a means to
reproduce their own life. When Marx and Engels write that men are
distinguished from animals not by some abstract principle
("consciousness, religion, anything else you like," but by their
mode of production it is because the human species is maintained in
its existence by and through the production of animal life,
including our own material life ruled by objective necessity. The
human species is the underlying mode of production that in
capitalism produces the appearance of a division between man and
animal as well as undoes this opposition by producing new forms of
life and organization beyond mere animal life that can only be fully
emancipated under communist production (conscious life activity).
[1] "Clearly the
increased concentrations of income that have emerged under
technological advance and global competition, have rekindled the
battle between the cultures of socialism and of capitalism—a battle
some thought had ended once and for all with the disgrace of central
planning. But over the past year, some of the critical pillars
underlying market competition arguably have failed" (Greenspan
n. pag.).
[2] This shift was officially formalized at the "The Idea of
Communism" conference in London March 2009 at which Žižek, Badiou,
Hardt and Negri participated.
[3] Žižek's "dialectical materialism" is the opposite of the
dialectical materialism of Engels. Dialectical materialism in
Engels' writings is the philosophical basis of Marxism because it
represents the only consistent understanding of materialism which
explains how change enters being not from a spiritual beyond, as
Hegel imagined, but from the motion of matter itself, which is
thought to be static and inert in "mechanical materialism"
(empiricism). It represents the principle that "the concept of a thing and its reality, run side by side like two
asymptotes, always approaching each other yet never meeting" (Letter
to Conrad Schmidt 1895), or, in other words, that our concepts are
abstractions of material reality with which they do not "coincide"
but nevertheless "correspond" in a "circuitous" way
("asymptotically"). As Engels' explains such an approach is
necessary so as not to fall into the false consciousness that our
concepts are merely pragmatic "fictions." As Lenin put it,
dialectical materialism is a "guard against mistakes and
rigidity" ("Once Again on the Trade Unions" 70-107), such as
the dogma that the relation
of concepts to reality is arbitrary (i.e., eclecticism), because
dialectical materialism maintains the principle that although
truth "is something we cannot ever hope to achieve completely" the
continual approximations made toward it are an "indicator of its
connection with human wants," its "use and connection with
the surrounding world," or, in other words, it demonstrates how the
"thing-in-itself" is always a "thing-for-us." Žižek's "dialectical
materialism" should more accurately be called an "eclectical
immaterialism" because behind all the examples, jokes, films,
biographies, philosophers, etc. he rehearses to illustrate the
(gray-on-gray) theme of the traumatic Real is the principle that "a
reduction of the higher intellectual content to its lower
economic... cause" (Parallax
View ix) is "bad" epistemology because it covers over the
"absent cause" of ontology (the Lacanian "lack" that drives desire)
which "eludes" representation, or, in other words, "the materiality
of ideology." Such an interpretation makes "dialectical materialism"
a trope of desire that occults need in his writing and, as in all
ideology, mystifies the social.
[4] Such a leap "outside" history is of course already "inside" the
discourse of anarchism which can be traced through the writings of
the Young Hegelians, to Stirner, Nietzsche, and Sorel, through the
Surrealists, the College of Sociology (Bataille, Benjamin), and the
Situationists, a text that moreover has always put itself forward as
dissenting from the "orthodoxies" of dissent and a "third way"
between capitalism and socialism and whose libertarian discourse has
itself become the official ideology of the neoliberal state
(deregulation). Žižek, however, has taken to cloaking it as
revolutionary Marxism ("Repeating Lenin" n. pag.). But for Marxism,
"the history of all hitherto existing society is the history of
class struggles" between "oppressor and oppressed" (Reader 473-4). Hence it follows that "there is no middle way (for
mankind has not developed any 'third' ideology), and generally
speaking, in a society torn by class opposition there could never be
a non-class or an above-class ideology" (Lenin,
What Is To Be Done? 41).
[5] The result of Žižek's rejection of Marx's labor theory of value
is bourgeois ideology: "I don't believe Bill Gates is exploiting his
workers because he pays them relatively well" ("Monstrosity of
Christ" 1:11:53). In short, exploitation is not a matter of
production but market exchange that disappears when the terms of
exchange are "fair." I leave aside how Žižek has already undermined
the logic of "fair" that allows him to conclude there is no
exploitation when he says that the logic of profit is "arbitrary"
because it is determined through the use of juridical force
(copyright). What is behind Žižek's illogic is the (ideo)logic of
capital that mystifies the source of value in human labor.
[6] This is perhaps most obvious in Žižek's justification of the 2008
bank bailout in which he argues that it was necessary given that the
"real economy" depends on the "virtual economy" in the sense that
everything has first to be financed in order to be produced (Tragedy
14); an ideological inversion characteristic of the capitalist
system that in fact makes exchange-value a priority over use-value
and thereby gives finance capital executive power in determining the
social distribution of resources. Leaving aside the fact that the
bailout has not stimulated the "real economy" and unemployment
continues to grow at an unprecedented rate, financial capital is not
productive capital that is invested in labor and machinery to
realize surplus-value but speculative capital that simply shifts
money around and re-distributes already produced surplus-value.
Žižek’s inversion of the "real" into the "virtual" economy dissolves
labor as the source of value into speculative financial transactions
as if capital were the source of value. What is Real is thus the
"bottom line" incontestable Truth of the market ("virtual economy")
over meeting people's needs for health care, education, housing,
communications, and economic stability ("real economy"). The reality
remains, however, that the "virtual economy" of financial
speculation emerges out of the "real economy" due to the falling
rate of profit relative to investment in the production process,
which is why the bailout has not stimulated investment and produced
jobs as advertised.
[7] See my "Designing Consent for Capital" (forthcoming).
[8]"Pettism" is an example of how bourgeois ideology "affects the
nerves" as Lenin is reported to have said regarding music, and
portrays animal life in such a way that "makes you want to say kind,
silly things, to stroke the heads of the people" under conditions in
which "you mustn't stroke anyone's head, you'd get your hand bitten
off" (Gorky, Lenin 44-5), so instead you (buy and) pet a
companion animal.
[9] Wendy and Lucy is part
of a new genre of writings/films like The Road (Cormac
McCarthy/dir. John Hillcoat), Never Let Me Go (Kazuo
Ishiguro/dir. Mark Romanek), Time of the Wolf (dir. Michael Haneke), and Children of Men
(P.D. James/dir. Alfonso Cuarón), that deal with traditional science
fiction themes (post-apocalyptic world, cloning, etc.) but in the
codes of realism, which have as their primary effectivity the
defamiliarization of the present and the immediate in terms of an
overdetermining but "absent cause." Like much of contemporary art
what the new hybrid-genre of "sci-lit" does is throw the audience
in media res and compel
the viewer to make sense of a fundamentally ambiguous narrative in a
ruined world full of the ghosts of narratives past that have lost
their substantive power to compel belief.
It is as if the sci-lit text puts the viewer in the place of
a child who while pressured to make sense of her surroundings is not
in a position to have the means to do so and is thus compelled to
invent her own framework of understanding.
Such an intelligibility can also be seen to be at work in the
"twee" aesthetic that has become so iconic in contemporary pop art
(Mark Ryden, Marcel Dzama, Anthony Goicolea,… )—traceable to the
"outsider" art of Henry Darger—that depicts adult themes in a naďve
way, as if all previous frames of reference of those "supposed to
know" have ossified and yet because events still demand to be made
sense of by being given a narrative form it must at the least be
modest and humble. The insistence on narrative having a "meaning" in
the wake of the impossibility of substantive consensus in a media
saturated environment is what makes contemporary art, at least at a
formal level, post-postmodern.
It is not massive "incredulity" toward "grand narratives"
that makes it impossible for them to secure belief, as Lyotard
defined the postmodern condition. Rather, it is the opacity that
ideology must of necessity assume as it is forced to manage the
unmet needs of the masses which is compelling them to believe that
another world is needed that militates against any substantive,
decided, consensual, meaning. And yet, the Left insistence on the
invention of an "imagined" narrative of community in the context of
its estranged forms in its willful ignorance of labor reflects the
ideology of contemporary cyber-capitalism as a regime of
"immateriality" in which knowledge rather than labor is considered
productive of value. The "immaterial" ideology is itself, however, a
reflection of the increasing ratio of "constant" (dead labor) to
"variable" (living labor) capital in the production process (Marx,
Capital 307-19).
In other words, it is the estrangement and appropriation of
labor that explains the alienation of human agency in social
consciousness which imagines agency as being "immaterial" and change
as merely a change in ideology. In the immaterial ideology the
material is an effect of knowledge (techne)—it
is "spirit" that moves the world not labor. For more on these issues
see my Cultural Theory After the Contemporary (2011).
[10] The Road also alibis capitalism in the way it, through
its many product placement ads, represents the products of consumer
culture (Coca-Cola, Cheetos, Vitaminwater,
etc.) as "life saving" and fails to show the connection of commodity
production with the causes of the apocalyptic event in the wake of
which the story takes place (Berman 87).
[11] "The dog and the horse, by association with man, have developed
such a good ear for articulate speech that they easily learn to
understand any language within their range of concept. Moreover they
have acquired the capacity for feelings such as affection for man,
gratitude, etc., which were previously foreign to them. Anyone who
has had much to do with such animals will hardly be able to escape
the conviction that in many cases they now feel their inability to
speak as a defect, although, unfortunately, it is one that can no
longer be remedied because their vocal organs are too specialized in
a definite direction" (Engels, Dialectics 173).
Works Cited
Althusser, Louis. Lenin and Philosophy. New York: Monthly
Review Press, 1971. Print.
Badiou, Alain. The Century. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2007.
Print.
Benhabib, Seyla. Critique, Norm and Utopia. A Study in the
Foundations of Critical Theory. New York: Columbia UP, 1986.
Print.
Benjamin, Walter.
Illuminations. New York: Schocken, 1977. Print.
Berman, Sarah. "The Year in Film." Adbusters Jan./Feb. 2010:
87. Print.
Clough, Patricia Ticineto, and Jean Halley. Eds.
The Affective Turn: Theorizing the Social. Chapel Hill: Duke
UP, 2007. Print.
De Man, Paul. The Resistance to Theory. Minneapolis:
Minnesota UP, 1986. Print.
Derrida, Jacques.
Dissemination. Chicago: Chicago UP, 1983. Print.
---. Positions. Chicago: Chicago UP, 1981. Print.
---. The Animal That Therefore I Am. New York: Fordham U.P.,
2008. Print.
Eagleton, Terry. After Theory. New York: Basic Books, 2003.
Print.
Engels, Frederick. "Letters on Historical Materialism."
The Marx-Engels Reader. Ed. Robert C. Tucker. New York:
Norton, 1978. 760-68. Print. Engels, Frederick. "The Part Played by Labour in the Transition From
Ape to Man." Dialectics of Nature. Trans. Clemens Dutt. Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1972. Print.
---. "To C. Schmidt." 12 March 1895. Letter 240 of Marx and Engels:
Selected Correspondence. Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing
House, n.d. 562-66. Print.
Fernández-Armesto, Felipe. "The Rise of Dog Identity Politics."
New York Magazine. 24 Jan. 2010. Web. 26 Feb. 2010.
Food, Inc. Dir. Robert Kenner. Per. Gary Hirshberg, Michael
Pollan, and Joel Salatin. Magnolia Pictures, 2008. Film.
Foucault, "Nietzsche, Genealogy, History."
Language, Counter-Memory, Practice. Ed. Donald F. Bouchard.
Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1977. 139-164. Print.
---. The History of
Sexuality: An Introduction. New York: Vintage, 1990. Print.
Gorky, Maxim. Lenin. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1967. Print.
Greenspan, Alan. "Markets and the Judiciary." Sandra Day O'Conner
Project Conference. 2 Oct. 2008. Web 1 May 2010.
Hall, Gary. New Cultural Studies: Adventures in Theory. Ed.
Clare Birchall. Atlanta: Georgia UP, 2007. Print.
Haraway, Donna. The Companion Species Manifesto: Dogs, People,
and Significant Otherness. Chicago: Prickly Paradigm Press,
2003. Print.
---. When Species Meet. Minneapolis: Minnesota UP, 2008.
Print.
Hegel, G. W. F. The Phenomenology of Mind.
New York: Harper & Row Publishers, 1967. Print.
Lenin, V.I. "Once Again on the Trade Unions."
Collected Works. Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1974. 32:
70-107. Print.
---. "What Is To Be Done?"
Collected Works. Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House,
1974. 5: 347-530. Print.
---. What Is To Be Done?: Burning Questions of Our Movement.
New York: International Pub., 1986. Print.
Marx, Karl. Capital. A Critique of Political Economy. Volume
I. Trans. Ben Fowkes. New York: Vintage Books, 1977. Print.
---. "Contribution to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right:
Introduction." CollectedWorks. Moscow: Progress Publishers,
1976. 3: 182. Print.
---. "Critique of the Gotha Programme."
Collected Works. Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1984. 24:
75-99. Print.
---. Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844. Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1974. Print.
---. Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy
(Rough Draft). New York: Penguin Books, 1993. Print.
---, and Frederick Engels. The German Ideology. Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1976. Print.
---, and Frederick Engels. "The Manifesto of the Communist Party."
Collected Works. Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1984. 6:
476-519. Print.
---, and Frederick Engels. The Marx-Engels Reader. Ed. Robert
C. Tucker. New York and London: Norton, 1978. Print.
Mau, Bruce. perf. The 11th Hour. Dir. Nadia Conners and Leila
Conners Petersen. Nar. Leonardo DiCaprio. Warner Bros., 2007. Film.
Negri, Antonio, and Michael Hardt.
Commonwealth. Cambridge: Belknap Press, 2009. Print.
---. Multitude: War and Democracy in the Age of Empire. New
York: Penguin, 2004. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, Walter Arnold Kaufmann, and R. J.
Hollingdale. The Will to Power. New York: Random House,
1967. Print. Saussure, Ferdinand de. Course in General Linguistics.
Eds. Charles Balley and Albert Sechehaye. Trans. Wade Baskin. New York:
McGraw Hill, 1966. Print.
Saunders, Frances Stoner. The Cultural Cold War: The CIA and the
World of Arts and Letters. New York: New Press, 2001. Print.
Smith, Terry. The Architecture of Aftermath. Chicago: Chicago
UP, 2006. Print.
"The Green Apple." Narr. Brad Pitt.
e2: The Economies of Being Environmentally Conscious. PBS.
2006. Television.
The Road. Dir. John Hilcoat. Per. Viggo Mortensen, Charlize
Theron, Robert Duvall, and Kodi Smit-McPhee. Dimension Films, 2009.
Film.
Turkel, Sherry. Life on the Screen: Identity in the Age of the
Internet. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1997. Print. Vološinov, V. N. Marxism and the Philosophy of Language.
Trans. Ladislav Matejka and I. R. Titunik. Cambridge: Harvard UP,
1993. Print.
Wendy and Lucy. Dir. Kelly Reichardt. Perf. Michelle Williams,
Lucy, Will Oldham, Wally Dalton, and Gregg Schmitt. Warner Bros.,
2008. Film.
Wolfe, Cary. What Is Posthumanism? Minneapolis: Minnesota UP,
2010.
---. "Posthumanities." CaryWolf.com. N.p. 2006. Web. 24 Feb. 2010.
Zavarzadeh, Mas'ud. "Post-Ality: The (Dis)Simulations of
Cybercapitalism." Transformation 1: Marxist Boundary Work in
Theory, Economics, Politics and Culture.
Washington D.C.: Maisonneuve Press, 1995. 1-75. Print.
---, and Donald Morton. Theory, (Post)Modernity, Opposition.
Washington, D.C.: Maisonneuve Press, 1991. Print.
Žižek, Slavoj. "An Interview with Slavoj Žižek: 'On Divine
Self-Limitation and Revolutionary Love'." Joshua Delpech-Ramey.
Journal of Philosophy and Scripture. Volume 1, Issue 2, Spring
2004, pp. 32-8.
---. "Ecology-A New Opium for the Masses." lacan dot com. 28
Nov. 2007. Web. 14 Mar. 2010.
---. First as Tragedy, Then as Farce. New York: Verso, 2009.
Print.
---. "Learn to Live Without Masters." Naked Punch. 3 Oct.
2009. Web. 8 Mar. 2010.
---. On Belief. New York: Routledge, 2001.
---. "Repeating Lenin." lacanian ink. Web. 24 Feb. 2010. ---. "The Monstrosity of Christ: Paradox or Dialectic?" 21 Sept. 2009. Harvard Book Store and The Brattle Theatre. Web. 23 April 2010. ---. The Parallax View. Cambridge: MIT, 2006. Print. |
THE RED CRITIQUE 14 (Winter/Spring 2012)
REDCRITIQUE.ORG
Back