Machine-Thinking and the Romance of Posthumanism Kimberly DeFazio
ONE
Rooted in the exploitation of labor, capitalism has
always produced deep contradictions in social life, and it has therefore
always required ideologies that explain away those contradictions.
Throughout the capitalist era, certain ideological strategies become
dominant when the advance of technology, driven by private accumulation,
brings about qualitative changes that upturn everyday life, as happened,
for instance, in the early stages of industrialization and resulting
urbanization in Britain in the late eighteenth century; at the height of
European imperialism at the turn of the 20th century; and in the shift
to "post-industrial" capitalism in the 1960s and 1970s in the global
North. At such times, dominant discourses absorb the material
contradictions of the social into the immaterial realm of language,
feeling and thought—where the sharp lines of class are blurred, the
mechanistic aspects of life are made fluid, and the "ugliness" of the
city is replaced by the aesthetics of nature.
In the 21st century, global capitalism's
commodification of all aspects of life has reached new heights,
requiring new modes of explaining away the material roots. From cloning
and bioengineered food, to ever-newer forms of human-technological
hybrids, to overfishing and industrialization of slaughterhouses, to the
privatization of public sources of water and the selling of "hot air"
(which makes it possible for rich nations to avoid lowering emissions),
to the "synthetic biology" by which biocapitalists like J. Craig Venter
hope new living creatures will be produced to substitute fossil
fuels—there is no aspect of social or natural life that is immune from
the market. Capital's endless and inherently crisis-ridden drive to
accumulate profit has, on the one hand, led to a new scramble among
nations of the global North to privatize the world's dwindling natural
resources regardless of the human and ecological consequences. What this
competitive drive has lead to, among other things, is the scientific
explorations of new bio-horizons: what Venter calls a "new industrial
revolution" (Pollack). On the other hand, the most recent effects of
capitalist crisis—beginning with the 2007 housing market crash—have been
used to justify further privatization of social resources, leading to
historically unprecedented cuts in wages, employment and social programs
throughout the global North.
It is not surprising, then, that cultural theory
has become more and more concerned with the relation between human and
non-human life and with the instrumentalities used by the former to
control the latter. Broadly characterized by a "posthuman" displacement
of humanist priorities of reason, rationality and Cartesian dualism, at
the center of which is a human subject constructed as fundamentally
different from and superior to non-human animals and life and capable of
developing reliable knowledge of and control over the objective world—a
wide range of cultural writing today has become concerned with the
increasing subjugation of nature to human calculation and control, and
call for a new inquiry into the relation of the human and its other.
Some, like Giorgio
Agamben, address the increasing efforts of the state to control and
manage all aspects of human and non-human life (Homo
Sacer; The Open). Others,
like Antonio Negri and Michael Hardt, focus on the efforts by
corporations to privatize the knowledges, affects and technologies that
have been developed through the collective energies of what they call
the multitude: the efforts to enclose the digital commons in the
interests of a powerful few (Commonwealth). Graham Harman goes
so far as to suggest that the "being" of tools is constitutive of all
being in the contemporary moment (Tool-Being),
while Peter Menzel and Faith D'Alusio celebrate the displacement of homo
sapiens by the notion of robo sapiens (Robo
Sapiens). Among one of the most
popular developments in contemporary posthumanist theory, animal
studies, writers like Cary Wolfe, Donna Haraway, Kelly Oliver, and
Matthew Calarco, taking their cue from Derrida's later writings (i.e.,
The Animal That Therefore I
Am), address what is for them the
instrumentalizing and unethical discourses of humanism, which justifies
its violence toward non-human species by its epistemological centering
of the human: the "anthropological machine" (Agamben, The Open).
But what drives the "new industrial revolution"
(Venter) is what drove the "old" one: the use of technology to
appropriate surplus labor (the source of profit) at the point of
production. Profit is not derived from "nature" but labor: in order for
nature to become a commodifiable resource, it must become transformed by
human labor, which is itself a dialectical outcome of nature. This is
another way of saying that the commodification of life on such a
planetary scale today is only possible on the basis of the
commodification of human labor power. Biocapitalism is first and
foremost a regime of wage labor.
Contemporary cultural theory's concern with the
effects of capitalism on non-human life, however, has mystified
capital's material roots, and one of the central means by which this has
been accomplished is what I call machine-thinking.
Machine-thinking treats capitalism as an
instrumentalized mode of thinking:
a mechanized mode of knowing which subjects all (non-) human life to its
logic. Whether this logic is understood in the more positive terms of
Henry Jenkins, John Johnston or Bernard Stiegler, who sees a fundamental
connection between humans and technology and suggests that "The human
invents himself in the technical by inventing the tool" (Stiegler,
Technics and Time 141), or in
the "negative" terms of those like Paul Virilio or Horkheimer and Adorno,
who suggest that "A technological rationale is the rationale of
domination itself. It is the coercive nature of society alienated from
itself" (Dialectic of
Enlightenment 121), machine-thinking (mis)reads as the instrumentalization of society what is in reality the
marketization of society—by
which I mean the domination of all aspects of life by exchange value and
the subordination of use value (which meets human needs, including the
need to preserve the earth's diverse ecological systems) to profit.
These misreadings, in effect, transcode the
material relations of production under capitalism into the immaterial
and translate the labor relations of the machine into instrumental
reason. In different idioms, such discourses consequently turn the
problem of capitalism into the problem of technologization and what
Heidegger, one of the twentieth century's most influential
machine-thinkers, calls "technē, a process of reflection in
service to doing and making" ("Letter on Humanism" 218). On these terms,
at stake is not exploitation but instrumentalization. Contemporary
discourses see capitalism in terms of what Heidegger identifies in "The
Question Concerning Technology" as the truth of technology in the modern
era: its "enframing" logic (325), which ensures that in a technological
age "even the cultivation of the field has comes under the grip of
another kind of setting-in-order, which sets upon nature. It sets upon it in the sense of challenging it.
Agriculture is now the mechanized food industry, air is now set upon to
yield nitrogen, the earth to yield ore, ore to yield uranium, for
example" (320).
But the focus on the way that, in a technological
society, neither nature nor humans are meaningful in and of themselves
but as means toward an end—or the way that, as Heidegger puts it, an
instrumental approach "expedites in that it unlocks and exposes" and is
fundamentally oriented "toward driving on the maximum yield at the
minimum expense" (321)—isolates technology from both the broader
material conditions in which it is developed and the class interests it
serves. For capital "drives on the maximum yield at the minimum
expense," not because of the "dialectic of enlightenment," as Horkheimer
and Adorno contend, but for the purposes of private accumulation. Humans
are "set upon" nature in order to maximize surplus labor for the owner
who buys the labor of others and makes a profit from it. To put this
another way, humans are set upon nature because they are set upon
themselves. And because the material relations of society set the terms
for the relations between humans and nature, only under fundamentally
changed relations between humans can humans develop new relations to
nature and non-human species.
Yet the solution to the instrumentalization of
human and natural life for Heidegger and other (neo)romantics like
Derrida, Wolfe, and Calarco is not a fundamental change in social
relations but a return to the "material" as non-instrumental reason (the
non-reason of nature, the body, feeling, spirit, "poeisis," the
non-human, and so on): in short, a de-materialized material. Theorists
of capitalism-as-machine-thinking construct a post-rational linguistic
realm of higher values which are assumed to exceed restricting codes and
conventions. For "mechanical" modes of thought which focus on
classifying being and the "metaphysics" of presence (essentialism), they
substitute speculative, fluid concepts which foreground becoming, flux,
and hybridity—what Goethe refers to as "morphology" and Derrida calls
the "double-session" and later "l'animot."
For the Cartesian separation of subject and object they posit a subject
which cannot be extricated from its embeddedness in the world except
through a violent act of human(ist) abstraction.
Machine-thinkers, in other words, oppose the
effects of capitalism by blurring social boundaries and essentializing
epistemological distinctions in an effort, not to transform capitalism,
but to find a freer mode of life outside of the social (outside the
city). It involves, as Wolfe puts it in his annotation of R.L. Rutsky's
theory of posthumanism, "participat[ing] in—and find[ing] a mode of
thought adequate to—'processes which can never be entirely reduced to
patterns or standards, codes or information'" (What
is Posthumanism? xviii). This is a (not so distant) echo of
Thoreau's romantic desire to "wander far beyond... the narrow limits" of
restricting codes and conventions in everyday life, into the realm of
what he calls "Extra vagance!":
the fulfillment of the "desire to speak somewhere without bounds"
(Walden 270).
Not coincidentally, the "nature" that thereby
becomes valorized by critics of machine-thinking is, in effect, a
rewriting of romantic discourses. As much as theorists locate themselves
beyond naďve (humanist) constructions of nature, nature in contemporary
theory is ultimately a bio-fantasy of a nature "outside" of and
fundamentally disruptive of the social relations of production. In
opposition to techne, in other words, machine-thinkers oppose (natural)
"life" itself ("bios"). Along these lines, in some contemporary
posthumanist discourse, "nature" betrays a "viral" or "mutational logic"
that "exceeds and encompasses the boundary between the living or organic
and the mechanical or technical" and thus becomes "parasitical" (Wolfe,
What is Posthumanism?
xviii-xix)—a "natural" logic that is represented as breaking the bounds
of existing (social) thought but that ends up being a new species of
deconstruction. Leaving aside for the moment posthumanism's updating of
deconstruction, one of the key points here is that rather than changing
the relations in which life is lived, the new battle cry of the left
centers on new ways of thinking
about life as excessive of human relations. Machine-thinking is in
effect a romantic means of disappearing the social. Life is
re-articulated as "machine" and "nature," and as a consequence, what
makes both—social labor—becomes a fiction.
I argue that such rewritings of capitalism as
machine-thinking are part of a long line of romantic writings of the
social which emerge with particular force at times of economic crisis.
Romanticism, I argue, is not merely a particular historical
manifestation of a literary sensibility. It is a broader response
(literary, philosophical, cultural and political) in the
post-Renaissance West to the contradictions of capitalism: contradictions which romanticism
reads in terms of science and technology and, in particular,
instrumental rationality. To put this another way, the translation of
the material contradictions of capital into the ideal (and in particular
"machine thinking") is a structural feature of capitalism. It is rooted
in the way that capital, as it develops, increasingly "resolve[s]
personal worth into exchange value, and in place of the numberless
indefeasible chartered freedoms, has set up that single, unconscionable
freedom—Free Trade," one of the central consequences of which is that
"for exploitation, veiled by religious and political illusions, it has
substituted naked, shameless, direct, brutal exploitation" (Marx and
Engels, Manifesto of the Communist
Party).
Romanticism has always challenged the effects of
capitalist relations (giving it a semblance of radicality) but not its
root cause (exploitation). In this vein, Emerson, for instance, argues
that "Poetry is the consolation of mortal men," because they "live
cabined, cribbed, confined in a narrow and trivial lot—in wants, pains,
anxieties and superstitions, in profligate politics, in personal
animosities, in mean employments—and victims of these; and the nobler
powers untried, unknown" ("Poetry and Imagination" 37). "A poet comes,"
Emerson continues, "who lifts the veil; gives them glimpses of the laws
of the universe" (37-8). And what the poet reveals, according to Emerson,
is that reality is only the phenomenal appearance of a higher, spiritual
reality. Romantics like Emerson confine their understanding of
capitalist conditions to its alienating effects and use of technology in
the city (the space of the most developed technology and class
divisions). They therefore misread capitalism as primarily a rigid,
homogenizing and instrumental way of thinking. Poetry thus "consoles"
men, for Emerson, because, through it, the "veil" of phenomenal reality
is lifted to reveal a symbolic universe which resists the
instrumentality (i.e., the placing of ends before means) of modern life.
Which is another way of saying that Emerson reduces capitalism to
something that cannot be changed, only thought about differently. The
concern, in other words, is with the ways in which, as Heidegger puts
it, a technological age "take[s] thinking itself to be a technē,
a process of reflection in service to doing and making" ("Letter on
Humanism" 218). Nothing—and no one—is meaningful in and of itself, but
for something else (a means toward an end). This reading of instrumentality de-historicizes and de-materializes instrumentality. In focusing only on the how of instrumentality—how instrumental thinking equates the valuable with the efficient, with efficaciousness—the reasons why this has become the dominant logic in capitalism fade into the background. In fact, the marginalization of the why in cultural theory has become grounds for treating Heidegger (among others) as a militant against the metaphysics of origin and religious origin in particular. Along these lines, Timothy Clark affirms that, for Heidegger, "Ultimately, like human existence itself, it [Being] is without a 'why' (has nothing we might recognize as a meaning): it happened because it happened" (34). Yet in the name of the destruction of religious and metaphysical origin, Heidegger has been instrumental in updating spiritualism and, in effect, in dismantling the knowledge of material origin. Poetry, for both Emerson and Heidegger, re-thinks
the contemporary, and, in a more or less overtly religious language,
produces a subject that recognizes the world's (material) insignificance
from the vantage point of a higher immaterial reality. "Every natural
fact," Emerson writes in Nature, "is a symbol of some
spiritual fact" (26).
The mode of romanticism I address in this essay is
ultimately a class response to the
contradictions of capitalism
which it reads in terms of science and technology, and in particular
instrumental rationality. To be more specific, this romantic
construction of nature (including nostalgia for the past) is a response
to the fact that, as Marx and Engels argue,
The bourgeoisie, wherever it has got the upper hand, has put an end to
all feudal, patriarchal, idyllic relations. It has pitilessly torn
asunder the motley feudal ties that bound man to his "natural
superiors", and has left remaining no other nexus between man and man
than naked self-interest, than callous "cash payment". It has drowned
the most heavenly ecstasies of religious fervour, of chivalrous
enthusiasm, of philistine sentimentalism, in the icy water of
egotistical calculation. It has resolved personal worth into exchange
value, and in place of the numberless indefeasible chartered freedoms,
has set up that single, unconscionable freedom—Free Trade. In one word,
for exploitation, veiled by religious and political illusions, it has
substituted naked, shameless, direct, brutal exploitation.
The bourgeoisie has stripped of its halo every occupation hitherto
honoured and looked up to with reverent awe.
It has converted the physician,
the lawyer, the priest, the poet, the man of science, into its paid wage
labourers. (Manifesto 486-7)
Romantic machine-thinking is a response to
capital's relentless conversion of people into wage-laborers—a process
which, in times of crisis, hits the "middle" sectors of class society (i.e,
intellectuals, the petit-bourgeois) particularly hard. Facing the deep
insecurity of their class position yet ultimately opposed to the working
class struggle to transform capital, the first line of defense among
intellectuals facing growing economic and social crisis has always been
the turn to the immaterial, and often the irrational. That is to say,
romantic idealism is a discursive relay of the displaced
petit-bourgeoisie—and, in the face of the rising conflict between labor
and capital, signals a retreat into and call for some "other way of
life" in order not to engage the material conflicts of the present. This
is why it surfaces with such force during moments of intensified crisis.
Thus, for instance, the rise of romanticism in late 1700s to the early
1800s is also the time of revolutionary upheavals, the intensified
destruction of peasant life, as well as the consolidation of the early
industrial city with its obvious class contradictions with life in the
early factories (before the period of "social reform" from the 1840s on
in England)—which romanticism sees in terms of the excesses of
Enlightenment rationality and the logic of quantification.
Although developed in many idioms, what these
romantic responses ultimately share, I argue, is not so much a nostalgia
for the past—this is a secondary effect—but an idealist logic which
ultimately erases the human as shaped by labor. The importance of
critically re-examining such discourses (which often claim to represent
a radical departure from dominant thinking) is that, by disappearing the
relations of labor, and replacing the material with the immaterial, the
ideological work of machine-thinking is to forestall transformative
change. It substitutes for the revolution of
material structures what Wordsworth, in his Preface to
Lyrical Ballads, calls "throw[ing]
over [familiar incidents] a certain colouring of imagination" (597) or
what Matthew Calarco, in reference to posthumanism, calls a "revolution
in language and thought" (Zoographies
6): a substitution that has become increasingly appealing to
ruling class interests at times of deepening social contradictions.
Because the substitution of material change for
change in thinking has strong ties to the machine-thinking of Heidegger,
I focus next on Heidegger's critique of instrumental reason, which
treats the objective world (of work, labor, tools) as an extension of
the subject and turns the subject into a particular mode of thinking (of
Being). I later go on to examine contemporary posthumanism's reading of
the animal in relation to Heidegger and argue that, despite the
self-distancing of posthumanists like Derrida, Calarco and Wolfe from
Heidegger, their theory of human/animal relations is a species of
Heideggerian machine-thinking, at the center of which is an ineffable
materialism. Posthumanism, I argue, is a reinvention of familiar
discursive strategies whose ultimate effect has always been to
de-materialize the social at the very moment materialist analysis of the
social totality is necessary to understand capitalist crisis and how to
transform it. This is, I suggest, one of the main reasons for the swift
emergence of posthumanism in the publishing industries of the global
North in the wake of the crisis of the 1990s tech boom and especially
since the collapse of the housing market in 2007—both of which are
symptoms of a much deeper structural crisis of global capitalism.
TWO
Heidegger is not only the "master" theorist of what
is now dominantly called "theory" (the speculative discourses informed
by poststructuralism) but he is a touchstone for virtually all
discussions of posthumanism today. His significance is related to his
efforts, in the wake of the first global crisis of capitalism, to
account for that which simultaneously grounds all thinking (Being) and
yet has remained excessive to philosophy. Faced with the first World War
and consequent massive devastation throughout Europe as the imperialist
nations settled colonial boundaries, Heidegger was forced to confront
the very nature of human being, on new terms. For him, the traditional
modes of understanding human existence were unable to account for the
realities of modern life and had to be subjected to a systematic
"destruction" in order to move forward. His "fundamental ontology" thus
attempted to disclose the true basis of Being from which people had been
alienated since the Socratics. The loss of individuality, for Heidegger,
results, not from material relations, but from a failure to understand
the true nature of being.
One of the theoretically influential aspects of
Heidegger is the way that his writing combines an interest in the
(ruins) of the everyday and a mystical mode of reading "beyond" the
material appearance of the world. To address this aspect of Heidegger's
writing, we can turn to his discussion in
Being and Time of the everyday
use of a particular tool, engaging in a particular activity such as
hammering. Graham Harman suggests, in fact, that Heidegger's "theory of
equipment contains the whole of
Heideggerian philosophy, fully encompassing all of its key
insights," and its importance lies in the way that it encourages "a
ruthless inquiry into the structure of
objects themselves" (Tool-Being
15). Although Harman suggests that through a re-reading of Heidegger it
is possible to return to the world of objects, and represents his own
re-reading of Heidegger as "a military campaign driving back toward the
surface of reality" (6), not a
transcendent one, I argue that whether Heidegger is addressing the world
of "objects" or the human thinking that grasps their being or human
being itself, the material world quickly recedes in Heidegger's
writings, into the ethereal, inaccessible, and ineffable (into the
subjective), a central aspect of his machine-thinking.
Consider, for instance, Heidegger's well-known
passage on the hammer, in which he writes,
In dealings such as this, when
something is put to use, our concern subordinates itself to the
'in-order-to' which is constitutive for the equipment we are employing
at the time; the less we just stare at the hammer-Thing, and the more we
seize hold of it and use it, the more primordial does our relationship
to it become, and the more unveiledly is it encountered as that which it
is—as equipment. The hammering itself uncovers the specific 'manipulatability'
['Handlichkeit'] of the hammer. The kind of Being which equipment
possesses—in which it manifests itself in its own right—we call "readiness-to-hand"
[Zuhandenheit]. Only because
equipment has this "being-in-itself' and does not merely occur,
is it manipulable in the broadest sense and at our disposal... If we
look at Things just ‘theoretically', we can get along without
understanding readiness-to-hand. But when we deal with them by using
them and manipulating them, this activity is not a blind one; it has its
own kind of sight, by which our manipulation is guided and from which it
acquires its specific Thingly character. (98)
Addressing the act of "hammering" of course
automatically signals Heidegger's interest not only in the more
"concrete" (i.e., "material" or "worldly") aspects of the everyday but
also the world of work, labor and tools: the realm of production. And
yet, as I mentioned, the effect of Heidegger's reading of "hammering" is
precisely the spiritualizing of the material: bringing back the
centrality of the individual subject's thinking as the basis of the
real.
Contrasting "unveiled" "encountering" with
(Cartesian) theoretical knowing of the objective world, Heidegger
suggests that the experiential act of
hammering itself attunes one
to the "primordial" nature of the relation of human to hammer, the
hammer's being as "readiness-to-hand." Grasping this readiness-to-hand
is not something that can be achieved by any theoretical approach, but
by the intuitive experience itself. For, on these terms, manipulating
the hammer provides the subject with an (immediate, non-theoretical)
"sight" which itself gives the objects manipulated their "thingly
character." And this itself is the effect of the particular (intrinsic)
being of the hammer's relation to Dasein, which reveals itself to the
human subject in the act of hammering.
To put this another way, in his theorization of
production ("hammering"), which is centered on the subject, the world
and products of labor increasingly recede and disappear. As he puts it
elsewhere, the approach he highlights "is not a way of knowing
those characteristics of entities which themselves are [seinder
Beschaffenheiten des Seienden]; it is rather a determination of the
structure of the Being which entities possess. But as an investigation
of Being, it brings to completion... that understanding of Being which
belongs already to Dasein and which 'comes alive' in any of its dealings with entities" (95-6; emphasis
added). It is not about the material relations of human being or even
the relations of humans and tools that matters here. It is instead what
using equipment tells the subject (Dasein) about the innermost nature of
human existence. Thus the focus, as Dasein, becomes the interiority of
the subject, the subject thinking about the hammer—or the "other" hammer
in the subject's thoughts. Heidegger's is a spectral hammer, which seems
to attain its more authentic ("primordial") sense of being precisely to
the extent that its roots in the material world are suppressed. The
subject's "rootless" interior "sight" is then posited as
(de-)establishing, negating, the qualities of the material world. The
material world (that matters) ends up being an effect of the thinking
subject. Consequently, as his discussion unfolds, the hammer looses more
and more of its "hardness" (that which links it to the outside world) to
the sensuousness of language and thinking (which renders that outside
world increasingly ineffable). The sensuousness of language here combats
the instrumentalities of the material world. We are led throughout Being and Time, and especially
in his later writing on poetry, to the materiality of language, which
guides the subject, never to any "outside" reference (i.e., the
objective world of history) but to an ever deeper interiority of meaning
within language. Language, after all, is for Heidegger "the house of
Being" ("Letter on Humanism" 217). And it is, more specifically, "[t]he
liberation of language from grammar into a more original essential
framework" (218) that constitutes the most "primordial" mode of language
(poetry). Through the meditation on "grammarless" language (outside of
social convention), Heidegger's writing removes from language any
material resistance, and dwells in the sensuousness of the signifier.
What starts out as a gesture to the worldliness of the world, in short,
ends up in the worldless subject.
This is because, in the first place, the being of
hammering has little to do with the physical, material aspects of the
hammer (its use value, which is in part related to a products' physical
properties) or empirical properties which could be "tested"
scientifically ("characteristics"). Even less so is the hammer's
readiness-to-hand for Heidegger the result of its being a product of
labor, used under specific historical relations of property which enable
it to be "ready-to-hand" for those who sell their labor to survive (the
"in order to" of commodity production). This is not coincidental. For,
central to his treatment of the "hammer" is the double-move of first
reducing materialism (which argues that consciousness is determined by
material relations) to mechanical materialism (the Newtonian thinking
which treats the world as independent, isolated, and unchanging
objects), and then, having done this, rejecting "materialism" as a rigid
mode of thinking incapable of grasping the complexity and changes of
social or natural life. As Heidegger explains, "When analysis starts
with such entities [as Things] and goes on to inquire about Being, what
it meets is Thinghood and Reality. Ontological explication [then]
discovers... substantiality, materiality, extendedness, side-by-side-ness,
and so forth" (96). But even on these terms, he argues, "the entities
which we encounter in concern are proximally hidden"(96). This is
because, to address things in terms of their materiality or their
"substance" (127), Heidegger argues, is to posit "an idea in which Being
is equated with constant presence-at-hand" (29), an idea based on
entities as "That which enduringly remains, really is" (128).
Conflating idealist and materialist theories of substance, and thus
representing materialism as positing an unchanging, eternal theory of
the objective world, Heidegger suggests that the materiality of the
object is an appearance only. Advancing a critique of present-ism that
will later become central to textualism and posthumanism, Heidegger
suggests that empiricism, rationalism and historical materialism—all of
which, in different ways, assume the existence of an "object" which can
be "known" by a "subject" which is distinct from the object—have
obscured the true being of entities by focusing only on appearances of
objects (their "presence"). But these presentist appearances conceal
deeper-lying dynamics (of becoming, of relations between presences and
absence) that exceed attempts to conceptualize (or "fix") them.
However,
it is important to recall that "presence" for Marx is not a metaphysical
fiction but a material relation. The presence of an object is not simply
a matter of its empirical reality, but the historical conditions which
make that object available for humans in the first place. Hammering, on
these terms, is not a transhistorical relation to being, but a
historical relation to the conditions of labor. Hammering with one's own
tool, in order to meet one's own means of subsistence, has a different
meaning than hammering with a tool that you have been hired to use and
whose product you will have no control over or property in, because both
the hammer and the product are privately owned. For Marx, the material
"presence" of objects is their material relations, which are submerged
in the everyday.
Whereas Heidegger posits the outside as the
extension of the inside—the internalization of the thinking subject,
which "negates" the outside world—for Marx, the interior is the
extension of the exterior. "My general consciousness," Marx argues, "is only the
theoretical shape of that
which the living shape is the
real community, the social
fabric" (Marx, Manuscripts 105). Because Marx is oriented toward the outside—the inside is the
outside—the material world never loses its materiality, and labor is
established as the movement of history. Production, for Marx, is the
"externalization" of the subject, the "objectifying" of the self in
labor, under definite conditions. There is thus a dialectical relation
between subject and world. "Objectification" (in the language of the
Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844) is an outward
movement, as opposed to Heidegger's absorption of the external world
into the subject. In human's objectification in the activity of
production, the subject "externalizes" not only the individual self, but
the social relations in which the self is a laboring subject. The
subject's agency is not therefore primarily a matter of
thinking-as-negating but producing-as-bringing-into-being, and only by
virtue of this agency of labor is the subject also a thinking subject.
Heidegger's language, by contrast, is inwardly oriented, hence the
outside world becomes increasingly ineffable, and this is, I argue, one of the central
effects of machine-thinking—the evaporation of the social divisions of
the outside world in the sensuousness of language, in poiesis.
In the most basic terms, of course, both Heidegger
and Marx agree that, as Marx puts it, "at the present day
general consciousness is an abstraction from real life and as such
antagonistically confronts it" (Economic
Manuscripts 105)—that is, that consciousness is alienated from
reality. But Heidegger's hostility to the "general consciousness" is
deeply tied to his romantic treatment of technology and technological thinking.
"In utilizing public means of transport and in making use of information
services such as the newspaper," Heidegger argues, "every Other is like
the next. This Being-with-one-another dissolves one's own Dasein
completely into the kind of Being of 'the Others' in such a way, indeed,
that the Others, as distinguishable and explicit, vanish more and more.
In this inconspicuousness and unascertainability, the real dictatorship
of the 'they' is unfolded' (Being
and Time 154). Elaborating his machine-thinking, Heidegger here
perhaps makes most manifest his rejection of the working class "mass,"
within whom (it is assumed) all individuality is lost and one sinks into
"averageness" and "mediocrity." Deeply aware of the growing
international power of the organized working class, not only in the
Soviet Union, but throughout Europe and even in the US after the first
world war, what Heidegger "sees" in the strengthening urban proletariat
is an indistinguishable mob threatening unique authenticity
(individuality), which is a code for private property. As a result, it
is not the property relations which strip workers of the means of
production, forcing them to work for someone else that Heidegger sees as
the root problem of the working class. It is instead the machines that
cause the working class to lose their individual freedom and
individuality, not workers' class relation to machinery but the
machinery itself (along with its instrumental thinking). Thus the homogenization
(abstraction) of labor by capital gets translated as "leveling down" and
"averageness" which themselves are then equated with "publicness." The
"city" (the space in which technology is most concentrated) then is
rejected because it "controls every way in which the world and Dasein
get interpreted" (165). Nature in turn becomes the romantic space in
which "every difference of level and of genuineness" and the "heart" of
matters are experienced outside of social interpretation—as the
"ineffable." This of course leads Heidegger, in his later
writings, to become more and more concerned with the consequences of
technology's "enframing" logic for nature. As he puts it in "The Question Concerning Technology," in a
technological age "even the cultivation of the field has comes under the
grip of another kind of setting-in-order, which
sets upon nature. It sets upon
it in the sense of challenging it. Agriculture is now the mechanized
food industry, air is now set upon to yield nitrogen, the earth to yield
ore, ore to yield uranium, for example" (320).
For Heidegger, the conflict between "consciousness
and real life" (Marx) is ultimately a mode of thinking that has not been
attentive to Being, and can be remedied with a new mode of thinking. For
Marx, by contrast, this results from the social relations in which the
products of human's labor are alienated from them. Only a society in
which a few own the means of production can others be in a position that
they not only must sell their labor to survive but under conditions in
which they have no control over or property in their product of labor.
"How would the worker come to face the product of his activity as a
stranger," Marx asks, "were it not that in the very act of production he
was estranging himself from himself? The product is after all but the
summary of the activity, of production... In the estrangement of the
object of labor is merely summarized the estrangement, the alienation,
in the activity of labor itself" (73-4). For this reason, there can be
no moving beyond the situation in which people are alienated from their
productive activity ("hammering") unless the social relations of
production are transformed. But Heidegger bypasses change of material
relations by suggesting that hiding behind (or "alongside") the
materiality of the everyday world of tools is a deeper, more elusive
being—one which renders the relation of subject and object far more
"ambiguous" (subjective) and which can be accessed only through
intuition. For Heidegger, the more authentic approach to Being can only
take place through the "qualitative experience" constitutive of
being-in-the-world as against the "abstract" (concept) or theory.
It is, however, only abstraction that allows one to
grasp the abstract material relations underlying experience. To
repeat, the hammer is material not because of the qualities of its "thingness"
(the argument of mechanical materialism and matterism) but because of
the abstract social relations which both produce it and which determine
its applications and its "meanings." In the guise of putting forward a
new notion of the (immaterial) "material," Heidegger's argument is a
means of dismantling the concepts needed for materialist explanation of
the world. Without concepts which make connections between apparently
fundamentally different entities and phenomena, there is no way to
understand the labor relations which position people in structurally
similar ways much less the economic laws which compel capital to exploit
labor. Heidegger forgets, in other words, that "pre-reflective" or
"primordial" experience is the space of ideology. Focusing only on the
excessive "experience" of labor thus directs attention away from the
material world which shapes experiences and onto the subjective ways of
thinking about experience as an isolated "in itself": precisely the
ideological ways of thinking capital fosters so as to inhibit working
people from identifying common (class) interests and collectively
fighting for them.
Ultimately, then, as Lukács put it, Heidegger
represents "the philosophical 'third way': the claim to be above the
antithesis of idealism and materialism (which he terms realism)" (Destruction of Reason493). That is to say, "He claimed to be
arguing an objective doctrine of Being, an ontology, but he then defined
the ontological essence of the category most central to his world on a
purely subjectivistic basis, with pseudo-objectivistic expressions"
(496). The real value of Heidegger's writings has thus been their
ideological function for capital. Confronting catastrophic
contradictions, Heidegger sought to understand the nature of human being
not in the social relations of production, but in "primordial" ways. He
launched a major offensive against instrumental thinking—what was for
him a metaphysical will to presence that impeded humans' ability to
grasp their true relation to Being—and developed new ways of
comprehending the embeddedness of the subject in its environment, so as
to blur the boundary between subject and object that had been a
cornerstone of Cartesian and Newtonian thinking. But in so doing, he
separated instrumentality from the relations in which instruments come
to dominate human life and human thinking. His ontology, which in the
light of its broader historical context functioned to establish a
philosophical basis for the recovery of a defeated nation, has operated
since then, in diverse ways, to absorb the contradictions of the
imperialist era of capitalism into the realm of a more ephemeral and
fluid conceptualization of existence. Thus, while posthumanism
ostensibly critiques Heidegger's "essentializing" of the human, as I
will address later on, his idealist treatment of being and
machine-thinking informs the entire structure of posthumanist thinking
and is a testament to its ultimately conservative role in the 21st
century.
THREE
It is in some sense inevitable that with class
divisions sharpening, contemporary cultural theory's effort to avoid
addressing class while criticizing capitalism's instrumentality, has
also led to a return to the romantic writings of Heidegger. Like
Heidegger's theory of the human (which becomes, in his writings,
absorbed into the sensuousness of language), posthumanism's re-thinking
of the human in the face of material contradictions leads it to a
philosophical third way. Because my reading of posthumanist discourse
goes against the grain of posthumanists' self-representation, it will be
useful to first address the terms of posthumanism more closely to unpack
some of the aspects of its idealism and its connection to the
machine-thinking of Heidegger.
According to its proponents, posthumanism represents a break from older
discourses in the humanities, which are no
longer capable of responding to the emerging realties of biocapitalism.
What is no longer explanatory, these theorists argue, are the humanist
discourses which have established divisions between humans and animals
and, more broadly, between humans and the non-human (nature, machines,
etc.). Theorists like Donna Haraway, for instance, argue for the
erasure of what she calls "the Great Divide" between "human" and
"animal" and abandoning of the traditional humanities and their
anthropocentric, hierarchical binaries of Cartesian thinking—which, in
placing the thinking subject above the body and embodied feeling,
marginalize "the animal" (When Species Meet). Along these lines,
in Zoographies Matthew Calarco
writes that contemporary discourses seek to show, on the one hand, that
"the wide variety of beings referred to as 'animal' cannot be reduced to
any simple (or even relatively complex) set of shared characteristics"
(3), and on the other, that "traditional human-animal distinctions,
which posit a radical discontinuity between animals and human beings"
are unviable (3). "[T]o privilege the historical time of the
humanities," Robert Markley argues, making more explicit the
machine-thinking on which posthumanist discourses depend, "is to remain
entangled in the double-bind of philosophical and techno-scientific
modernity, endlessly engaged in rituals of purification (the focus on
speciation as classificatory mastery) and hybridization (defining
coevolution by Dr. Dolittle–ing the animals)" ("Species, Identity
Politics, Ecocriticism" 99).
Among the central questions in the posthumanist field of animal studies
(what Calarco, like Cary Wolfe, following Derrida, call "the question of
the animal") are, he argues, those concerning the being of animals, and
the human-animal distinction. For posthumanists, in other words, "the
human-animal distinction can no longer and ought no longer to be
maintained" (emphasis in original 3). Along these lines, Wolfe
argues that "the question of the animal" is "'at
this moment'…not just any difference among others; it is, we might
say, the most different difference, and therefore the most instructive"
(Zoontologies 23).
Why has the animal question emerged "at this moment"? One of the
fundamental assumptions of posthumanism is that new phenomena—i.e., new
studies into language acquisition and use in animals, into cognitive and
affective similarities of humans and animals, new technologies
hybridizing humans and machines, humans and animals, new investigations
into DNA—are the effects of particular ways of knowing and their
manifestation in particular uses of technology. In a new twist of
machine-thinking, posthumanist discourses suggest that new discoveries
in science and technology—e.g., zoology, biology, microbiology,
genetics—along with challenges to traditional humanities within such
disciplines as philosophy and literary studies have brought about
challenges to older paradigms of human-animal relations that make more
ethical relations possible. Derrida articulates this matrix of
assumptions when he writes that "It is all too evident" that
"traditional forms of treatment of the animal have been turned upside
down by the joint developments of zoological, ethological, biological,
and genetic forms of knowledge,
which remain inseparable from techniques of intervention
into their object, from the transformation of the actual object, and
from the milieu and world of their object, namely, the living animal" (The
Animal That Therefore I Am 25; see also Wolfe's Introduction to
Zoontologies x-xiii). Implicit
here is the argument that contemporary forms of knowledge have broken
free of the Cartesian framework of rationalism (the "bad" science of an
outdated capitalism), according to which it was possible to clearly
separate subject from object and which define the human in relation to
its distinct capacities for reason. New knowledges (the "good" science
of contemporary capitalism) call these suppositions into question by
establishing deeper similarities between human animals that undermine
the notion that humans possess any distinct traits. For what Agamben
calls "the anthropological machine" posthumanist discourses substitute
what Wolfe calls a "viral" logic that "exceeds and encompasses the
boundary not just between human and animal but also between the living
or organic and the mechanical or technical" (What
is Posthumanism?xviii). Which is another way of saying that what
posthumanism advocates is a more fluid ("viral," "parasitical") machine.
Derrida's comments above, it should be noted, are a quasi-appeal to the
material which quickly turns the material into the ideal, and secondary
effects into the primary cause. New realities, Derrida suggests, are the
effect of knowledge and its "techniques" on the one hand and on the
other the (cultural) "milieu" of the world—both of which are
superstructural aspects of economic relations. That is to say, not only
is the new research into animals revealing more similarities between
humans and animals dependent upon (Cartesian) study of the animal object
by the human subject, but the studies into human-animal relations are
not in any way "outside" of capitalist accumulation, as Derrida
suggests; they are, in fact, made possible by labor and the labor
relations that relentlessly divide the working class and owners while
producing "results" that posthumanists treat as hybridizing or
disrupting all inter- and intra-species distinctions. In this way,
Derrida is able to address many of the new concrete realities of
capitalism, while at the same time isolating them from their roots in
the (human) relations of exploitation. For Derrida and other
posthumanists, as I have argued, the central task is founded on
(re)thinking: developing those knowledges that are capable of revealing
the inherently ambiguous nature of human-animal relations, and
critiquing those that presuppose any essential distinctions.It
is in this context of distinction-blurring posthumanist analysis that
Calarco devotes the first chapter of Zoographies
to a critique of Heidegger because, he writes, "It is my contention that
his work has served primarily to marginalize the animal question in
contemporary thought" (although Calarco admits at the same time that
many of the "questions and theses" of his critique "are fundamentally
indebted to the horizon of thought opened up by Heidegger" (15)). One of
the texts Calarco pays special attention to is the "Letter on Humanism,"
and especially its relation to Heidegger's earlier work. Whereas his
earlier writings attempt to develop an ontology that would "reorient the
human and biological sciences, as well as the university as a whole"
(31), the later writings, Calarco argues, are more "dogmatic" in their
insistence on a fundamental difference between humans and animals. For
instance, Calarco picks up on Heidegger's question in the (later)
"Letter," "whether the essence of the human being primordially and most
decidedly lies in the dimension of animalitas at all," as opposed
to humanitas (Heidegger, "Letter" 227).
Heidegger's question relates to metaphysics'
equating of the human with "animal
rationale," where the human becomes simply "one living creature
among others" (whose difference lies in its capacity to reason). The
problem with animal rationale,
Heidegger argues, is that this is already a metaphysical interpretation
of humans, which does not think "the essence of man... in its origin"
(227). It thus obscures the real difference of Dasein—which is
fundamentally human (and is not so by virtue of its reasoning capacity
but because of its relation to Being). For Heidegger, language is the
"house of being"; to be able to gain access to the dwelling of Being,
Dasein requires language, the "home that preserves the ecstatic for his
essence" (228) or "the clearing-concealing advent of Being itself"
(230). Only through language can one experience the "standing in the
clearing of Being I call the ek-sistence of man" (228). However,
Heidegger argues, "Because plants and animals are lodged in their
respective environments but are never placed freely into the clearing of
being which alone is 'world,' they lack language," and they thus lack
access to Being. In short, according to Heidegger, animals are
"separated from our ek-sistent essence by an abyss" (230). At stake in such statements for Calarco is not Heidegger's idealist ontology, but that "Heidegger uncritically accepts two basic tenets of ontotheological anthropocentrism: that human beings and animals can be clearly and cleanly distinguished in their essence; and that such a distinction between human beings and animals even needs to be drawn" (30). The issue here for Calarco and other posthumanists is the "essentializing" tendencies which characterize humanist thinking, and which Heidegger's later works more overtly display. Whether the "human" is understood as in idealist terms, as a "thinking" being (as in Aristotle, Descartes or Hegel), or in materialist terms of labor (Marx), from the standpoint of posthumanism, all forms of humanism are equally problematic on the grounds that, as Neil Badington puts it, humanism posits "an absolute difference between the human and the inhuman" (Posthumanism 4). On this basis, Cary Wolfe opposes the liberal humanist "speciesism" which attempts to "define a category of beings by its essence," so as to establish a fundamental difference and hierarchy between the human and nonhuman others (Animal Rites 32). Calarco thus says of Heidegger that he "offers nothing in the way of critique concerning the metaphysical tradition's drawing of the oppositional line between human beings and animals" (53). This is at the heart of the posthumanist critique of humanism: its more or less hidden anthropocentric nature of essentialism. Calarco thus shows in subsequent chapters how some of the very theorists to have addressed the animal question in a way that opens up pathways toward the erasure of human/animal binary nonetheless end up to a greater or lesser extent re-affirming the division and consequently essentialism. But how far beyond Heidegger do posthumanist discourses go? As I argued earlier, Heidegger's "third way" focus is in part on the "qualitative experience" constitutive of being-in-the-world against the "abstract" (concept). Central to Heidegger's replacement of materialism with ineffable materialism is the (familiar) critique of "theory" as a legacy of Cartesian separation of subject and object. Briefly returning to Being and Time, Heidegger emphasizes that, whereas "Being-in-the-world, as concern, is fascinated by the world with which it is concerned" (88), theoretical "knowing" of the world is characterized by "deficiency." He writes, "If knowing is to be possible as a way of determining the nature of the present-at-hand by observing it, then there must first be a deficiency in our having-to-do with the world concernfully. When concern holds back from any kind of producing, manipulating, and the like, it puts itself into what is now the sole remaining mode of Being-in, the mode of just tarrying alongside" (88). In other words, the subject/object relations of metaphysical knowing (theory) are based on the illusory separation of the subject from its world—as if the subject were "autonomous" (89) from the object. On this basis of subject/object relations, Heidegger renounces of course not only (idealist) rationalism, but the philosophy of materialism, which posits the existence of an external world independent of individual consciousness but which can be known through scientific analysis. The problem, according to Heidegger, is that a theory which assumes a difference between subject and object is a mode of being that "lets us encounter entities within-the-world purely in the way they look... Looking at something in this way... takes over a 'view point' in advance from the entity which it concerns. Such looking-at enters the mode of dwelling autonomously alongside entities within-the-world" (88-89). One finds the same concern in posthumanist discourses: the subject/object relations of traditional science have allowed the (human) subject to separate itself from the world in which it is integrally embedded. Hence the argument that all such distinctions as subject/object, human/animal, human/machine, and so on require vigilant deconstruction so as to show that we are all "mongrel" (Markley). That is to say, any standpoint from which one can separate subject from object, human from animal is a form of epistemological purification which not only falsely constructs divisions whose boundaries are established by their exclusions, but is a "utilitarian calculus" on the basis of which "all living beings" become "potentially means and not ends" (Wolfe). A broader point that needs to be made here is that, while for Heidegger the problem is the subject/object binary, and for posthumanists it is the human/animal distinction, what they all reject as metaphysical thinking is the logic of the "binary" which is the structuring principle of class society. Class societies, in which a few control the labor and products of others and thus have control over the lives of the majority, necessarily create cultural and conceptual divisions which codify these class relations. Conceptual divisions have their material roots not in the mind but in the world which the mind reflects, through more or less complex mediations. This is one of the basic principles of materialism: ideas are not the product of the (individual) mind; rather, social consciousness is shaped by social existence. Therefore changing how people think and thus act (whether to oneself, other humans, animals or the environment) requires changing the material divisions that produce othering. Philosophy which simply does away with conceptual distinctions in thinking, as Heidegger and other romantics do, not only gets rid of the very concepts (like "class," "exploitation," "determination") needed to understand the structuring principles of class society, but, in effect, displaces material change of objective conditions onto the subjective change of the individual. This is the essential politico-cognitive work that neoromantic theory does for capital. Whether through such concepts as Keats' "negative capability" Kant's "sublime," Heidegger's "Being" or "the question of the animal" that is the more recent focus of such writers as Derrida, Wolfe, and Calarco, romantic machine-thinking celebrates the dissolution of boundaries: between self and other, subject and object, philosophy and poetry, rich and poor, the social (as city) and nature. It constructs a post-rational linguistic realm of higher values which exceed restricting social codes and conventions. Boundaries, in romanticism, are viewed as the imposition of cultural codes and linguistic conventions that rigidly delineate, not as material (as effects of labor relations). It is through the replacement of "mechanical" concepts with speculative ones that romanticism blurs social boundaries and epistemological distinctions in an effort, not to transform capitalism, but to find a freer mode of thinking within it. As Wordsworth puts it in his Preface to Lyrical Ballads, it involves taking familiar incidents and "throw[ing] over them a certain colouring of imagination"—or, in the updated idiom of posthumanism, a "revolution in language and thought" (Calarco, Zoographies 6).
Heideggerian pre-reflective experience, like "the
question of the animal," is in short the space in which "abstract"
binaries like class (not to mention other social differences) evaporate.
By blurring lines, romantic theory seeks, as Heidegger puts it, "the
liberation of language from grammar" ("Letter on Humanism" 218), rather
than social transformation. To liberate language from grammar is of
course to free up thinking (from cultural bounds), to suspend the social
structures of language and, according to Heidegger, to come closer to
understanding Being. Grammarless language is thus the fantasy of the
plentitude of meaning outside of the social. No matter how adamantly
posthumanism condemns Heidegger's human-centered thinking, the very de-essentializing
strategies it deploys to challenge human-animal distinctions are
informed by the (Heideggerian) desire to escape existing social
conventions, through the relay of the animal.
FOUR As I have mentioned, left cultural theorists in the postwar period (like Calarco) have been simultaneously seduced by Heidegger's writing yet careful to mark their differences from him, especially in the wake of the exposure of his membership in the Nazi party in the 1930s. Like Calarco's, Derrida's critique of Heidegger's earlier writing is similarly nuanced (marking his essentialism, while simultaneously positing Heidegger as opening up the space for rethinking foundational questions). But Derrida's rereadings are particularly instructive in establishing the shift from his earlier textualist reading of Heidegger to the posthumanist critique, which actually incorporates the textualization of binaries into its own "new" methodology of reading humanism. In his early poststructuralist writings, Derrida emphasizes that at stake in Heidegger is "the dominance of an entire metaphorics of proximity, of simple and immediate presence, a metaphorics of associating the proximity of Being with the values of neighboring, shelter, house, service, guard, voice, and listening" ("The Ends of Man," Margins of Philosophy 130). In other words, Derrida's textual reading of Heidegger suggests that a close analysis of Heidegger's phenomenology reveals that "[i]nsofar as it privileges the 'authentic' (eigentliche) voice/speech that, as 's'entendre parler,' brings presence to light against the 'secondarity' or 'fallenness' of writing, it betrays the complicity with logocentrism that disables Husserl's phenomenology" (115). Heidegger, then, posits a metaphysical presence, which Derrida reveals to be a logocentric fantasy covering over a constitutive lack.
In Derrida's more recent re-reading of Heidegger
(i.e., The Animal That Therefore I
Am), what is at stake is not so much humans' purported "presence"
but the assumption that animals lack presence (a relation to world) that humans are assumed to have.
Like Calarco, Derrida now emphasizes that animals, for Heidegger, can
never stand in relation to other beings "as such" (in and of themselves)
because they are world poor; animals on this basis are merely living,
unlike humans. In other words, it is not the notion of presence that
Derrida is concerned with (deconstructing) but demonstrating that
positing a (uniquely) human presence is the basis upon which Heidegger
assumes a lack in animals that not only privileges the human but allows Heidegger not to have
to engage the ethical relations of humans and animals (undermining
Heidegger's emphasis on "care"). For Derrida, the being of animals in
Heidegger is
a trustworthy example of what
he calls Nur-Lebenden, that
which is living but nothing more, life in its pure and simple state. I
think I understand what that means, this 'nothing more' (nur).
I can understand it on the surface, in terms of what it would like to
mean, but at the same time I understand nothing. I'll always be
wondering whether this fiction, this simulacrum, this myth, this legend,
this phantasm, which is offered as a pure concept (life in its pure
state—Benjamin also has confidence in what can probably be no more than
a pseudo-concept), is not precisely pure philosophy become a symptom of
the history that concerns us here. Isn't that history the one that man
tells himself, the history of the philosophical animal, of the animal
for the man-philosopher? (22-23)
Through this re-reading of Heidegger, Derrida (once
again) situates "history" as a metaphysical fiction "man tells himself"
to give meaning to human life. But the concern is the way this
particular narrative arrives at its seeming coherence through the
exclusion of animal life (which is read by Heidegger as "nothing more
than" "pure and simple" life relative to the plentitude of human Being).
The great fiction here is human's capacity to reason as that which
distinguishes humans from animals. Consequently, according to Derrida,
at the very moment "when Heidegger's gesture is to move forward in the
direction of a new [i.e., post-Cartesian] question, a new questioning
concerning the world and the animal, when he claims to deconstruct the
whole metaphysical tradition, notably that of subjectivity, Cartesian
subjectivity, etc., insofar as the animal is concerned, he remains, in
spite of everything, profoundly Cartesian" (147).
For Derrida as for Calarco, then, the fundamental
problem with Heidegger is the (Cartesian) "abyss" he assumes exists
between humans and animals, which renders humans "purely" one thing and
animals another, and which posits the animal as lacking a presence only
humans are assumed to have. It is what allows, at the level of thinking,
human mastery over the animal and nature. But it is important to note
that posthumanism is not opposed to the notion of a constitutive abyss
per se. Rather, what it opposes is the presumption that a gap exists
between two entities that makes one essentially different from the
other. After all, Wolfe emphasizes Stanley Cavell's argument that
"language (and understanding, and knowledge) rests upon very shaky
foundations—a thin net over an abyss" (quoted in
Zoontologies 4). Similarly, Derrida celebrates the experience of
standing naked in front of his cat and becoming aware of the animal's "uninterpretable,
unreadable, undecidable, abyssal… secret" that puts Derrida to "shame" (The
Animal That Therefore I Am 12). Abyss here, in Derrida and Wolfe,
signals something beyond the reach of knowledge and understanding, and
is precisely that which exposes the "metaphysical" basis on which the
human/animal distinction lies; it is therefore to be understood as a
mark of Derrida's and Wolfe's "subtle" thinking as opposed to the
vulgarity of Heidegger.
This is another way of saying that posthumanist
readings of human-animal relations do not at all move away from the
speculative epistemology of textualism. Rather, they import
poststructuralist deconstruction of binaries as a means of introducing
the (now, for them, more "urgent") ethical question of the animal. The task of theory is no longer to
mark the "lack" that undoes all distinction, all concepts, but to mark a
"fullness" of animal being that exceeds the humanist understanding and
which, when brought to light, can reveal a common distinctionlessness of
all human/non-human life: a plentitude that (it is assumed) exists prior
to the rigid, essentializing distinctions that constitute the social.
This shift itself however needs to be addressed in
the context of the material contradictions in the wake of global (cyber)
capitalism. The focus on "lack" was part of the philosophical strategy
of disarming materialist concepts in the wake of the second World War and the
heightening of the Cold War. Textualism was, to put this another way,
the epistemology of the neoliberal era of de-regulation. Through the
lens of textuality, all concepts were rendered equally unstable and
untenable. On these terms, not only the "human," "progress" and
"science" (banners of the bourgeois Enlightenment) but "class" and
"exploitation," like all other social categories, emerged as thin
discursive constructs without any determinate relation to material
reality. Indeed, "determination" and the "material" were perhaps subject
to the most widespread deconstruction. The result was that the very
concepts needed to understand the increasingly global nature of capital
and its systematic subjugation of the working class to the international
relations of wage-labor, were rejected as "totalitarian" concepts. In
the place of materialist concepts, textualist-informed cultural
theory—which grew to become the dominant framework from the 1960s
through the 1990s—substituted difference, singularity, and jouissance.
"Materialism" soon became equated with the "materiality" of writing and
its subversion of all binaries, including the binaries of inside/outside
(on which historical materialism is based). Textualization, in effect,
did at the level of theory what transnational capital did at the level
of regulations and national boundaries: it subverted them so as to
expand the market and market-thinking.
Since the 1990s, however, not only have
poststructuralism's speculative aspects themselves come under increasing
criticism (see, for instance, the official eulogy for poststructuralist
informed "high theory" in the 2004 Special Issue of Critical Inquiry) and are now
widely discredited for being out of touch with contemporary social
realities, but economic contradictions have emerged as truly global
crises that threaten capitalism itself. To be sure, posthumanism is just
as invested in dismantling distinctions. Thus Calarco is highly critical
not only of Heideggerian essentialism but "semantic and ontological
realism that involves making sharp distinctions among different beings"
(38). And, moreover, deconstruction of conceptual binaries is always the
chief strategy in discrediting distinctions, especially distinctions
among species. Thus in Kelly Oliver's Animal Lessons, animals in
canonic romantic and philosophical texts are read as the exemplary
agents of deconstruction, as "biting back" the very texts that seek to
establish them as other: "In those passages in which they delineate what
distinguishes man from animals, both Rousseau and Herder turn to animals
to illuminate their arguments. Their animals do not merely serve as
examples against which they define man. Rather these animals belie the
very distinction between man and animal that their invocation seeks to
establish. As we will see, the examples and metaphors of animals that
inhabit these texts ape or mock assertions of any uniquely human
characteristics" (2). In an important sense, posthumanist discourses
reanimate textualism for the knowledge industry, thus making it
profitable again. But, again, the posthumanist emphasis is increasingly
a romantic reading of nature as "surplus," which foregrounds the
excessiveness and fullness of natural life, represented as violently
reduced by human concepts.
If (textual) "lack" has become less interesting to
cultural theory than the excessive plentitude of nature and the
non-human, this needs to be related to the unavoidably vivid
human devastation that global capitalism has quickly led to since
its "triumph" over Soviet socialism in the early 1990s—not only in the
global South and many former Soviet-bloc nations, but (especially
recently) in the very pillars of capitalist economies in the global
North. The technological advances that globalization promised would
result in more democratic societies have been accompanied by profound
social alienation and isolation and even deeper class inequality.
Globalization had promised a new era of freedom and prosperity, but "[i]n
reality," as Teresa Ebert writes in The Task of Cultural Critique,
globalization
has made wage labor (which is
missing from, for example, Derrida's discourse on globalization/mondialisation) the universal regime of work. It has suspended all
strong labor laws and finance regulations so that capital can travel
freely across national borders to invest, trade, and own property all
over the world, as well as set wages and receive huge tax benefits at
the expense of workers... It has used democracy as a cover for imposing
the free market on people of the world and transferring public wealth to
the private sector by commodifying water, healthcare, education, energy,
food and transportation. It has increased the gap between poor and rich
countries, ruined the environment, and turned the 'working day' into a
nightmare of unending exploitation for workers who, unprotected by any
laws, have only two options: consent to being exploited at an
ever-increasing rate or live a life of extreme poverty and want in
everlasting uncertainty. (136-37)
Posthumanist concern with the animal is a romantic
retreat to nature in the face of unprecedented social crisis. Through
it, the utter failure of capitalism to meet the worlds' social needs
(the deepening of class inequality between North and South and within
the North and South) is re-written as the (universal) failure of a
transhistorical "humanity" which has purportedly become alienated from
its roots in "nature." (Natural) plentitude has returned to fill the
void of living in the ruins of capitalism.
But, at the same time, this posthumanist retreat to
a ("new") nature also encodes a new energetic ethics which makes its
discourses seem not escapist but "activist" at a moment when theory can
no longer afford to seem out of touch. And, in this regard, far from
undoing all essentialized notions of the human, it installs a new
ethical essence to the human, who emerges out of posthumanism as that
species uniquely capable of recognizing the lack of fundamental
distinctions in nature and who makes ethical choices on that basis.
Posthumanism's ideological value, then, is that it serves the dual role
of making theory "matter" again in its focus on specific "material"
practices within capitalism that legitimate the destruction of nature
and abuse of animals (thereby giving posthumanism a veneer of activism),
while at the same time steering social activism and social theory away
from class. It displaces the heightening contradictions between humans
onto the relations between humans and animals. For the calculating logic
of instrumental reason, it offers a subversive mode of thinking that
purports to resist rigid binaries and hierarchies.
FIVE
Of course, as capitalism
advances, its technologies do become more alienating and isolating. As
Marx argues, through the relations of the market, concrete (specific)
forms of labor become exchanged on the basis of their being reduced to a
common value. The market is the mechanism through which the most diverse
types of labor (not only use of different materials and products but
different kinds of skills) are reduced to common units of value. In this
way, concrete labor is turned into an exchange value, which makes the
product of labor exchangeable with an enormous number of other kinds of
concrete labor.
All forms of (concrete) labor, Marx argues, "are reduced to one and the
same sort of labor, human labor in the abstract" (Capital
128). As Marx also shows,
however, exchange value—the "third thing" to which two different
products are reduced—is itself determined by the labor time necessary to
produce the two different products. The abstract value of the commodity
is determined by labor: the real source of value which is obscured by
exchange relations and the commodity form.
Central to the
abstraction of labor under capitalism is the fact that, for capitalists
to increase accumulated value (profit), more value has to be produced
than the laborer is compensated for: what is not compensated for is the
surplus value taken by the capitalist (a social process, Marx argues,
"that goes on behind the backs of the producers" [135]).
The role of technology under capitalism is to make the worker more
productive in the same amount of time, thereby allowing the capitalist
to appropriate more and more value while paying the worker the same
(proportionally less). "It is the compelling force of anarchy in social
production," Engels argues, "that turns the limitless perfectibility of
machinery under modern industry into a compulsory law by which every
individual industrial capitalist must perfect his machinery more and
more, under penalty of ruin" ("Socialism: Utopian and Scientific" 140).
But, as Engels continues,
the
perfecting of machinery is making human labour superfluous. If the
introduction and increase of machinery means the displacement of
millions of manual by a few machine-workers, improvement in machinery
means the displacement of more and more of the machine-workers
themselves. It means, in the last instance, the production of a number
of available wage-workers in excess of the average needs of capital, or
the formation of a complete industrial reserve army... Thus it comes
about... that machinery becomes the most powerful weapon in the war of
capital against the working class; that the instruments of labour
constantly tear the means of subsistence out of the hands of the
labourer; that the very product of the worker is turned into an
instrument for his subjugation" (140-41).
It is because of the more
immediately visible effects of technology that, in the early stages of
capital, workers attacked the machines that were putting them out of
work—for instance in the 1780s, when workers in the Leeds woolen
industry responded to their increased exploitation by destroying the
owners' new machines, and in the later Luddite movement of the early
1800s, in which textile workers attacked the looms (see J. F. C. Harrison's,
Society and Politics in
England, 1780-1960 [71-72] for the Leeds workers' Petition that
appeared in the newspaper at the time).
One of the consequences
of what Engels calls the "subjugation" of the worker by his product is
that advances in technology also de-skill the laborer. If not entirely
thrown out of work, the worker who used to have to carve wood to create
a chair, now presses buttons that guide a laser which cuts uniform
pieces of wood to be assembled, much of which is now done by the
consumer. Similarly, the computer technician who used to need to be able
to write codes to produce programs now uses ready-made templates, and
highly trained symbolic analysts are used for mind-numbing data-entry.
To put this differently, the drive for capital to increase exploitation
means that the constant "re-skilling" it requires of its workforce as it
introduces new technologies is thus always at the same time a
de-skilling—since the technology has made the production process even
more monotonous. Complex labor, in other words, is constantly being
reduced to simpler forms of labor. Capital is thus always introducing
newer (increasingly complex) technologies, which require new skills on
the part of workers and thus new "training." But the effect of these new
skills is not only to make the "training" increasingly short-term and
the workers more easily replaceable; it also, as Engels suggests,
creates an ever larger urban proletariat and reserve army of labor.
Technology, in short, becomes the focus in capitalist culture because
machinery, as Engels puts it, "becomes the most powerful weapon in the
war of capital against the working class." But, as Engels also
emphasizes, abstracting machines from the social relations of production
diverts attention from the class relations of machines.
In the early stages of
capitalism, when the divisions between capital and labor were only
beginning to emerge and therefore before the era of organized labor
(which connected the use of machines to the labor
relations of capitalism which
divide those who own the means of production from those who don't),
there was a historical basis for workers attacking the machines that put
them out of work. It was among the strongest and most direct means they
had of challenging their employers. Likewise, the intellectuals in the
late eighteenth century and early nineteenth century, who saw the
devastating effects of capital on the rural and industrial workers, were
especially concerned with the machine-thinking that accompanied
capitalism. In particular, they attacked the ways in which the machine
and machine-thinking took away human agency, rendering humans passive,
even conceptually and imaginatively imprisoned. In his critique of
Newton and the influence of Newtonian thought, Coleridge thus writes,
"Mind, in his system, is always passive—a lazy
Looker-on on an external world," and Coleridge insisted that "any system
built on the passiveness of the mind must be false" (Coleridge, Letter to Tom
Poole). Coleridge suggests that Newtonian mechanical thinking implied
people simply reflected their
conditions of life, rather than being reflective
or creative individuals who could not only think deeply about their life
(not just reflect it) but produce new ideas and new ways of thinking
about the interconnectedness of life. It did not allow for the
imagination, the thinking beyond what (materially) is. Similarly,
Blake's "There Is No Natural Religion," suggests that the idea that
"Man's desires are limited by his perceptions" (as associationalism and
empiricism proposes) means that "none can desire what he has not
perciev'd" (V). It implies individuals cannot think what has not been
already experienced, and that thinking is just a repetition of
experience, nothing else. To say that individuals are effects of their
environment, for Blake and other romantics, is to construct a reductive
model of subjectivity in which individuals are rendered passive subjects
of their environment. Hence the romantic proposal that individuals'
determination (their being, their consciousness) exceeds social
conditions; the human is thus more "at home," not in the city (the space
of the social), but in (spiritualized) "nature."
But in the same degree
that the division between capital and labor is more and more splitting
society, as Marx and Engels put it, "into two great hostile classes
directly facing each other" (Manifesto 474), bringing with it a more and more international and
class-conscious working class—in the same degree does the romantic focus
on machines and machine-thinking take on a reactionary, rearguard
character.
Heidegger's ontology and
contemporary romanticism are both elaborated in a fundamentally
different historical moment than the early romantics in the early era of
capitalism. Not only has the class divide continued to deepen with the
growth of capitalism, but the materialist theory of history has itself
developed to explain the historical origins of capitalism (and therefore
its inevitable end) and to discover that basis of capitalism is in the
unpaid labor of the worker which is extracted at the point of production
(i.e., that this surplus labor is the source of profit). It has
therefore become increasingly important for capitalism to produce modes
of thinking which challenge materialism and which thereby obscure the
roots of capitalism in surplus labor and prevent social struggles aimed
at making exploitation impossible. What Marx said of the
"critical-utopian socialists" holds true of neoromanticists: "although
the originators of these systems were, in many respects, revolutionary,
their disciples have, in every case, formed mere reactionary sects" (Manifesto 516). This is because, "in opposition to the progressive
historical development of the proletariat" they "hold fast" to the ideas
that reflected an earlier stage in the class conflict, and thus provide
no theoretical understanding for transformative social struggle. "They,
therefore, endeavour," Marx argues, "to deaden the class struggle and to
reconcile the class antagonisms" (499).
In fact, romanticism
takes on more and more directly the responsibility of combating
materialism and the class it represents. In this way, rather than
address the material conditions which reduce the individual to the
alienated worker, Heidegger—in the name of a more fundamental
ontology—treats materialism and science as the problem, and romanticizes
earlier periods when labor was more skilled and less alienated. It is
not the historical relations in which people "live so long as they work"
but the fact that these conditions (and all social explanations of these
conditions) make individuals the same that are his concern. Historical relations are reduced by
Heidegger to a transhistorical mode of being in which the subject
"itself is not; its Being has been taken away by the Others...
These Others, moreover, are not definite Others. On the contrary,
any Other can represent them" (Being
and Time 164). Thus the homogenization (abstraction) of labor by
capital gets translated as "leveling down" and "averageness" which
themselves are then equated with "publicness."
Heidegger's reading of
"Others" reflects a hostility to the material structures within which
people are located (as workers, as persons in particular social
functions) and their "functional" discourses, all of which reduce the
individual—to "averageness" (164) rather than make way for the authentic
primordial Self. But Heidegger's discourse on the "They" and
its relation to the city is symptomatic of the petit bourgeois fear of
dissolution into the "masses"—and loss of individuality in the
proletariat. In contemporary posthumanism too, as I argued earlier,
collective life is seen as a "loss" and nature is rediscovered as the
space of "difference."
One thus finds the pervasive interest in "zombie" culture alongside
posthumanist concern with animals and nature. Again, Heidegger provides
the overarching framework informing this trend. For the zombie is the
exemplary manifestation of the petit-bourgeois fear of the working class
other, "The They." As one writer notes in his critique of the dominance
of zombie shows and films, zombies "are mindless. They are
faceless. They are ugly. And they want to invade your home and feast on
your flesh," and they thus represent "an allegory for bourgeois
attitudes to and fears of the working class" ("Zombies and Ideology").
However, zombies also
"offer an opportunity for asserting superiority, mastery, contempt, and
individuality against the mass. Zombies are slow and stupid.
Humans are quick and intelligent. Zombies are limited by their reach.
Humans can use all manner of weapons." In this way, "zombie settings
offer a simple fantasy where one can assert the self—sometimes
heroically—against the world. You have to beat the undead hordes. Unlike
the ever-popular vampires, one cannot join them." It is in this sense
that, as Sam Leith argues, "Vampires are monsters of the right; zombies
are monsters of the left. Vampires are toffs; zombies are proles.
Vampires are individualists; zombies are the mindless, nameless,
faceless mob" ("Cultural Notebook: The Days of the Undead"). Thus,
"Vampires represent social climbing—you'll join the aristocracy after
you're bitten. The zombie is a leveller" ("Cultural Notebook: The Days
of the Undead"). To reiterate, Heidegger's
ineffable materialism is not only a resistance against the
"collective"—seen as lacking authenticity—it is a developed critique
against science/technology, and represents (in its claim to "authentic"
living, recovering access to Being, etc.) a backward and nostalgic
response to capitalism and the modern city as the space of heightened
class conflict—one reflective of the consciousness of the displaced
petit-bourgeoisie of the time threatened in their ways of life—the very
ones who would later support fascism as the "answer" to the crisis. His
later "mysticism" (the revelation of Being in "poetic" language as
inaccessible to science) is the "cultural excess" version of this
irrationalism, post-fascism, which is the spiritualist response to class
conflict.
SIX
The war against science in romantic cultural theory is a proxy war
against laws of social transformation, one which encodes the interests
of the petit-bourgeoisie—it protests the harsh realities of capitalism while evading
the necessity of its material transformation via revolution by positing
an "excessive element"—this "excessive element" (whether being,
difference, the animal, or...) is what makes it useful to
capitalism—because while it appears "transgressive" from one point of
view (negation of the existing), it inscribes within it the advance of
the forces of production while the social relations of property remain
intact. Put another way, it "assimilates" the changes required by
advancing forces of production to the framework of the old property
relations. But there is of course an untranscendable material "limit" to
this process of "adjustment"—when, to paraphrase Marx in the Preface to
A Contribution to the Critique of
Political Economy—the revolutionary letter comes due ("From forms of
development of the productive forces these relations turn into their
fetters. Then begins an era of social revolution."). Critique of
ideology is thus a way of facilitating this transformation by
heightening the contradiction—producing positive knowledge ("ontology")
of it (and the ways in which it is
obscured in bourgeois ideology).
As I have argued, romanticism has functioned at
critical junctures since the Enlightenment as an ideological pressure
valve: a means of dampening class contradictions and rendering ideology
critique crude and unnecessary (if not impossible). To prevent the
attack of the specific historical relations of production which deepen
social contradictions (the appropriation of surplus value), romanticism
instead attacks society as such
(as mechanical thinking) and appeals instead to society's other
("nature," "life itself," "the question of the animal," "Being"—from
which vantage points conceptual boundaries are to be perceived as empty,
"mendacious" [Nietzsche, "Truth and Lies in an Extra Moral Sense"]
artificial constructs).
Consequently, one of the important implications of
the posthumanist theorization of "humanism" (which imports Heidegger's
basic critique of metaphysics) is that it reduces all humanism to
Enlightenment humanism. In doing so, it also erases the materialist
theory of humanism, which is a critique of both Enlightenment humanism
and posthumanism. As Marx himself argues, "the
human essence is no abstraction inherent in each single individual. In
its reality it is the ensemble of the social relations" (Marx, "Theses
on Feuerbach").
The materialist theory of humanism, to put this
another way, is the theory of humans' place in the city: the site of
labor, consciousness, and history. This theory of humanism has in fact
always been put in question by capitalist ideology, the main task of
which is the use of culture to explain away (naturalize) the social
relations of labor from which capitalists profit. Whereas materialist
humanism is the articulation of the possible—freedom from necessity,
from the relations of exploitation—dominant theories of the
human/humanism are ultimately aimed at preserving existing class
relations. They do so by erasing the roots of humanity in labor and
treating the human instead as the subject of consciousness and reason
(i.e., the cogito, the speaking subject) or as the subject of
post-rational feeling and sensuousness (a subject of consciousness who
considers consciousness of feeling more important than rational
knowing).
What is thereby erased is that what humans do to
nature is a result of what humans do to themselves: "the exploitation of
man by man." It is the social relations and not epistemological and
cultural ones that shape material life, not only for humans but also for
all species. On these terms, the human subject is, above all, the
subject of labor. To theorize the basis of the human life in terms of
labor is to emphasize that, in "the working-up of the objective world"
of nature (humans' life-activity), humans make their life-activity "the
object of [their] will and [their] consciousness" (Marx,
Economic and Philosophic
Manuscripts 62). That is to say, "Man makes his life-activity itself
the object of his will and of his consciousness. He has conscious
life-activity" (62). And because his life-activity of production becomes
an object of consciousness, his life-activity "is not a determination
with which he directly merges" (62). This is the basis on which Marx
makes a distinction between humans and animals, between human
life-activity and animal life-activity (what he also calls the "natural
life"). Humans, in their productive life, are "self-conscious." The
animal, by contrast, "is immediately identical with its life-activity.
It does not distinguish itself from it," or, in short, it "merges" with
its life-activity (62). In fact, Marx writes, "It is just because of
this that [the human] is a species being. Or it is only because he is a
species being that he is a Conscious Being, i.e., that his own life is
an object for him" (62). Freedom and consciousness have an integral
connection here, since only because humans' life-producing activity is
an object of reflection "is [their] activity free activity" (62).
Insofar as the "human" is shaped by social
relations, in exploitative social relations, therefore, the "human
essence" is loss, deprivation, alienation, and contradiction. In the
case of capitalism, for the first time in history, the majority of
workers are "freed" in a "double sense." The mass of the working
population, lacking means of production to meet their own subsistence
needs, must sell their labor in order to survive. It is no longer the
production of use values—values that meet the needs of the society—but
exchange—values produced for the sake of private accumulation of profit.
In contrast to ancient societies, where "[t]he individual... can never
appear in the total isolation of the mere free labourer" (Marx,
Pre-Capitalist 81), with the generalization of commodity relations
(relations of exchange), the individual appears increasingly isolated—an
effect of the fact that "the worker finds the objective conditions of
his labour as something separate from him, as capital," which
also assumes that "the capitalist finds the workers as
propertyless, as abstract labourers" (86). The alienation
("estrangement") of the worker from the means and product of labor, as
Marx discusses in detail in the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, leads to further forms
of alienation, all of which derive from the separation of the worker
from her means and product of labor. Not only does the life-activity of
production become an alienating activity, ensuring that only when one is
not working does one feel truly "at home", but insofar as the
individual's realization of their life-activity in labor is alienated,
the worker is alienated from herself and others.
It could not be otherwise, then, that people's
self-estrangement becomes in turn the estrangement from others as well,
from the individual's "species being." Thus, although it is in
production that people confirm their species-life, estranged labor turns
consciousness of species life, of the central activity of species life,
into means of existence, into means of life (Marx,
Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts 59). "In tearing away from man the object of his production, therefore,
estranged labour tears from him his species life, his real species
objectivity, and transforms his advantage over animals into the
disadvantage that his inorganic body, nature, is taken from him" (63).
But, for Marx, the solution to alienation is not "retreat" into nature,
and idealized forms of community with animals and others, but fighting
for new social relations, and thus a new "human essence." It is in the
city (as the space of class conflicts) that this fight will take place.
It is quite telling, then, that, as Wolfe makes clear, for posthumanists,
human exploitation of humans stems from human exploitation of animals: "if we allow the human/animal distinction to remain intact... then the
machinery of speciesism and animalization will be available to use
against various subjugated groups, animal or
human, as history
well shows" ("Speciesism,
Identity Politics, and Ecocriticism"
102). Such arguments are especially effective (and hence
popular in the publishing industry) because, however much he may
criticize commodification, he ultimately takes critical pressure off of
the role of capital in impoverishing the world's majority and destroying
the environment, and places it (back) onto a "humanity" beyond classes.
The implication of Wolfe's argument is that struggles which prioritize
social equality are not only
unethical but futile, since there can be no social change between humans
until humans change their (more "fundamental") relations to animals. But human-animal relations, once again, are shaped by the social relations between people. And because it is the social relations that shape material life, not only for humans but also for other species, different forms of social organization consequently have different relations to animals. Social organizations based on collective ownership of property (as in early Native American tribes) have very different (in contemporary discourses, "ecological") relations to the natural environment, compared to societies based on the commodification of labor, in which all aspects of social and natural life are exchanged for private profit, regardless of the human or ecological consequences.
In claiming that human exploitation is caused by the exploitation of
animals by humans, not only does Wolfe therefore invert the real
relations conditioning human's lives and cover over historical
difference but he renders insignificant the great historical struggles
to transform class relations. It is not therefore surprising that the
argument for the "most different difference" of the animal is closely
tied to Wolfe's and other posthumanists' pragmatic, "ethical" argument
against the possibilities of an equal society—arguments which recall the
more politically reactionary aspects of romanticism. In discussing a
text by Paul Patton on the relations between horses and humans, for
instance, Wolfe writes that what makes Patton's analysis so important is
that "it helps to make clear the requirements and
obligations
of those hierarchical relations of power we do enter into (with animals,
with children, with each other) and draws our attention to how those
requirements are always specific to the beings involved, in the light of
which, he argues, the presumption of a one-size-fits-all notion of
'equality in all contexts' is 'not only misleading but dangerous'" (Zoontologies
xix). While the argument here seems to be a "progressive" call to be aware of the power dynamics that exist in all relations so as to treat others "ethically," its more emphatic claim is the deeply conservative argument against establishing "equal" conditions of equality for all, which casts principles for universal equality as "dangerous." Wolfe's pragmatism tellingly echoes the right-wing argument that efforts to provide "universal" health care, to establish federal laws requiring corporations to set caps on emissions or provide workers compensation are violent "impositions" on the local and the specific. It is in this context that Edmund Burke advocated as "natural" the "hereditary succession [of power] by law" and denounced the struggles for democracy around the French Revolution as a "perversion" of individuality: "We procure reverence to our civil institutions on the principle upon which nature teaches us to revere individual men," whereas "those who attempt to level, never equalise. In all societies, consisting of various descriptions of citizens, some description must be uppermost. The levelers therefore only change and pervert the natural order of things" (Reflections on the Revolution in France 30, 43)—a sentiment that has grown increasingly popular in the American political context. This is, by the way, why pragmatism is so effectively aligned with ethics: both highlight the specificity of context and the absence of any foundation of judgment and reject any notion of objective basis that might be used to explain the underlying relations of specificities. Ethics, to put it bluntly, is the ruse through which the "natural" existence of class relations is justified today. Ethics (individual acts of kindness, or what Foucault calls the "care of the self") is what follows once one has already decided that no serious social change is possible.
But, to have legitimacy, posthumanist ethics has to
claim for itself the mantel of radical. This puts it in a particularly
contradictory situation—its radicality can only be a gesture toward
radicality, which is to say a performance of radicality. Perhaps nowhere
is this performance more precisely captured than in these words from
Stanley Cavell in Philosophy the
Day After Tomorrow (2006), where he writes that Heidegger's
Being and Time and
Wittgenstein's Philosophical
Investigations are the two books most philosophically meaningful to
him because "each of them present[s] themselves on any and every page,
as carrying some urgent message for our lives, while neither raises any
issue that is explicitly about any act we ought to be doing or to
refrain from doing, or any rights we have denied, or any goods we have
neglected to share fairly" (219).
The sense of urgency without urgency... the
allusion to economic inequality without actually talking about it. These
are the banners of "left" thought in the global North, the rallying
message for the "radical" "theorists" who are neither radical nor
theoretical—the (upper) middle class intelligentsia who have benefitted
from global capital's pillaging of the working class worldwide and will
fight against any who threaten their "way of life," but who must at the
same time assume the stance of the "ethical" in the age of Obama. The
value of such modes of using language, as Cavell says about Emerson's
sentences, is that they "may attract us by their beauty or their
curiosity, and at the same time seem to play with our desire for some
transformative understanding" (220). This articulation perhaps outdoes
even Cavell himself in describing the mode of theory that has come to
typify contemporary romantic consciousness: a "playing" with
"transformative understanding." It is pretend philosophy, which
cynically knows it has no real interest in using theory to transform
everyday life, but writes in such a way to convince others it does:
conveying "urgency" without urgency (since, of course, those who have
the time and resources to "play" with philosophy must always feign
"urgency").
The argument that the question of
the animal is "'at this moment'... the most different difference, and
therefore the most instructive" (Zoontologies 23) cannot be separated
from the heightening economic contradictions which have once again
thrown into sharp relief the abyss dividing labor and capital. The
question of the animal is in fact a displacement of the "most different
difference" made possible by the inexorable dialectic of labor and
capital: a world free from exploitation. Works Cited
Adorno, Theodor, and Max Horkheimer. "The Culture
Industry: Enlightenment as Mass Deception." Dialectic of Enlightenment.
London: Verso, 1997. 120–67.
Agamben, Giorgio. The Open:
Man and Animal. Trans. Kevin Attell. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2004.
Blake, William. "There is No Natural Religion."
The
Complete Poetry and Prose of William
Blake. David V. Erdman, rev. ed. New York: Doubleday,
1988.
Burke, Edmund. Reflections on the Revolution in
France.1790. Ed. J.G.A. Pocock. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1987.
Calarco, Matthew. Zoographies: The Question of the Animal from
Heidegger to Derrida. New York: Columbia UP, 2008. Cavell, Stanley. Philosophy the Day After Tomorrow. Belknap Press of Harvard UP, 2006. Print.
Clark, Timothy. Martin Heidegger. New York: Routledge, 2002.
Coleridge, Samuel Taylor. Letter to Thomas Poole,
23 March 1801. The Collected
Letters of Samuel Taylor Coleridge. Vol.
II. Ed. Earl Leslie Griggs. 1956. 709.
"The Future of Criticism—A
Critical Inquiry Symposium." Spec. issue of Critical Inquiry 30.2
Derrida, Jacques. The
Animal That Therefore I Am. New York: Fordham U.P., 2008.
---. "The Double Session." Of Grammatology. Trans. Gayatri Spivak. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1978.
---. "The Ends of Man." Margins of Philosophy. Trans. Alan Bass. Chicago: University of Chicago P, 1982.
Ebert, Teresa.
The Task of Cultural Critique.
Urbana: U of Illinois P, 2009.
Emerson, Ralph Waldo. Nature.
The Complete Works of Ralph Waldo Emerson: Letters and Social
Aims. Vol. 1. Ed. Edward Waldo Emerson. Boston and
New York: Houghton Mifflin Co, 1904. 1-77. ---. "Poetry and Imagination."
The Complete Works of Ralph Waldo
Emerson: Letters and Social Aims. Vol. 8. Ed. Edward Waldo Emerson.
Boston and New York: Houghton Mifflin Co, 1904. 1-75. Print.
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang.
The Metamorphosis of Plants.
1790. Ed. Gordon L. Miller. Cambridge, MA: MIT, 2009.
Haraway, Donna. When Species Meet. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota P, 2008. Hardt, Michael, and Antonio Negri. Commonwealth.
Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 2009. Harman, Graham.
Tool-Being: Heidegger and the
Metaphysics of Objects. Peru, Il: Open Court Publishing, 2002.
Harrison, J. F. C. Society and Politics in
England, 1780-1960. New
York: Harper and Row, 1965.
Heidegger, Martin.
Being and Time. Trans. John
Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York and Evanston: Harper and Row, 1962.
---. "Letter on Humanism." Basic
Writings. Ed. Farrekk Krell. New York: Harper Collins,
1993. 213-265.
---. "The Question Concerning Technology."
Basic Writings. Ed. Farrekk Krell. New York: Harper Collins, 1993. 307-341.
Johnston, John.
The Allure of Machinic Life:
Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, 2010.
Leith, Sam. "Cultural Notebook: The Days of the
Undead." Prospect Magazine. 165
18 Nov.
2009. Web. 5 May 2011.
Lukács, Georg. Destruction of Reason.
London: Merlin Press, 1980.
Marx, Karl. Capital. Vol. I. Trans. B. Fowkes. New York: Penguin, 1977.
---.
Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844. Trans. Martin Milligan. Buffalo, NY:
---.
Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations. Eds. E. J. Hobsbawm and Jack Cohen. New York: ---. Preface. Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy.
Ed. Maurice Dobb. New York:
---. "These on Feuerbach." The German Ideology. Ed. C. J.
Arthur. New York: International,
Marx, Karl
and Frederick Engels. The Manifesto of the Communist Party. Collected Works.
Markley, Robert. Interview. "Species, Identity
Politics, Ecocriticsm: A Conversation with Humanists and Posthumanists."
The Eighteenth
Century 52. 1 (2011). 87-106.
Menzel, Peter and Faith D'Alusio. Robo Sapiens: Evolution of a New Species. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 2001.
Nietzsche, Frederick. "On Truth and Lie in an
Extra-Moral Sense." The
Portable Nietzsche. 1957. Ed. Walter Kaufman. New York: Penguin Books,
1977. 42–47.
Oliver, Kelly.
Animal Lessons: How They Teach Us
to Be Human. New York: Columbia UP, 2009.
Stiegler, Bernard
Technics and Time, 1:
The Fault of Epimetheus.
Trans. Richard Beardsworth and George Collins. Stanford: Stanford
UP, 1998.
Thoreau, Henry David.
Walden; O, Life in the Woods. New York: Holt, Rinehart and
Winston, 1948.
Wordsworth, William. Preface.
Lyrical Ballads. 1802.
William
Wordsworth. Ed. Stephen Gill. Oxford and New York: Oxford UP, 1984.
Pollack, Andrew. "His Corporate Strategy: The Scientific Method."
New York
Times. 4 Sept. 2010. Web. 4 Sept. 2010.
Virilio, Paul. The Futurism of the Instant:
Stop-Eject. Cambridge: Polity, 2011.
---. Speed and Politics: An Essay on Dromology.
1977. New York: Semiotext(e), 1986.
Wolfe, Cary. Animal Rites: American Culture, the Discourse of Species, and Posthumanist Theory. Foreword by W. J. T. Mitchell. Chicago:
University of Chicago P, 2003.
---. Interview with Lucinda Cole et al.
"Speciesism, Identity Politics,
and Ecocriticism: A Conversation with
Humanists and Posthumanists." The Eighteenth Century. 52.1
(Spring 2011). 87-106.
---. What is Posthumanism? Minneapolis: University of Minnesota P, 2010.
---. Zoontologies: The
Question of the Animal. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota P, 2003.
"Zombies and Ideology." Weblog entry.
A Very Public Sociologist. 6
Nov 2011. Web. 29 Nov |
THE RED CRITIQUE 14 (Winter/Spring 2012)
REDCRITIQUE.ORG
Back